Microsoft word - amlr.v9i1.morrison.final
Copyright 2011 Ave Maria Law Review
DUTY FIRST: TOWARDS PATIENT-CENTERED
CARE AND LIMITATIONS ON THE RIGHT TO
REFUSE FOR MORAL, RELIGIOUS OR
Jill Morrison and Micole Allekotte†
INTRODUCTION . 142
THE PROBLEM WITH REFUSALS . 144
A. Who is Harmed? . 146
B. What is the Harm? . 149
1. Physical Harms . 149
2. Emotional Harms . 155
3. Financial Harms. 157
4. Harms to Public Health . 158
5. Violation of Patient Rights . 161
C. How Common Are Refusals and How Often Are
Patients Harmed? . 162
II. ORIGINS OF THE PROVIDER'S DUTY . 164
A. Duty in Licensing . 165
B. Ethical Duty . 167
1. American Medical Association . 168
2. American College of Obstetricians and
Gynecologists . 169
3. American Pharmacists Association . 170
D. Recognition in Malpractice and Tort Law . 172
E. Duty of the Institution . 174
III. INADEQUATE PROTECTION OF PATIENTS . 175
† Jill Morrison is Senior Counsel for Health and Reproductive Rights at the National
Women's Law Center. Micole Allekotte is a Fellow for Health and Reproductive Rights at the National Women's Law Center. This paper is based on remarks made at the University Faculty for Life and Brigham Young University School of Law's Symposium on Rights of Conscience in Health Care, February 2010. The authors would like to thank Crowell & Moring LLP, Jeffrey Blumenfeld, Cliff Elgarten, Sarah Gleich and Jeffrey Davis for their pro bono research assistance to the National Women's Law Center and Gretchen Borchelt for sharing her expertise.
AVE MARIA LAW REVIEW
A. Legal Protections for the Right to Refuse and Impact on
Patients' Rights . 176
of Title VII . 181
IV. CONCLUSION: TOWARD PATIENT-CENTERED CARE . 182
A. Amendments to Existing Conscience Clauses . 182
B. Enforcement of Current Protections . 184
1. Informed Consent and Other Legally Enforceable
2. Title VII . 185
D. Provider Education
This Article argues that patient-centered care is the model from
which refusal policy should be derived. By entering the medical
profession, practitioners agree to a set of ethical principles which
ensure that they will put the patient's interests before their own.
Medical professionals have superior scientific knowledge and skill to
that of a patient, which puts them in a position of trust and influence.
Modern medical practice continues to move away from a model of
paternalistic physician control over patients towards patient decision-
making, which requires the professional to impart enough medical
information for the patient to make an informed decision. This Article
argues that it is ethically improper for medical practitioners to use
their position of influence that results from superior scientific know-
ledge to impose their moral preferences on the patient. Patient-centered
policy means that the primary goal of medical policy is to ensure
patient well-being, with secondary goals such as enhancing medical
workforce satisfaction. A refusal policy should maximize the situa-
tions in which an individual practitioner can follow his moral code
without interfering with the patient's rights to make moral and medi-
cal decisions and to access care.
A policy allowing for provider refusals is only appropriate when
it averts conflict between patient and practitioner morality by help-
ing practitioners to step away from treatment to which they object
without compromising the patient's ability to access the treatment.
However, where a conflict is inevitable, the patient has a superior
claim to the primacy of her health-care decision over the practitioner's
decision to refuse because the primary goal of medical care is patient
welfare; medical practitioner welfare is secondary. In practice, these
Fall 2010] TOWARDS PATIENT-CENTERED CARE 143
twin principles should result in a policy where practitioners retain the
duty to ensure that patients are provided with sufficient medical
information to allow the patient to make informed medical decisions
for herself and to ensure that the patient has access to care; these
duties cannot be abrogated by physician or institutional objection. At
the same time, the individual professional retains the right to pass
these duties on to another non-objecting practitioner; he does not
have the right to allow his moral objection to stand as an obstacle to
the patient obtaining information or care.
To actualize a system where medical professionals are generally
able to refuse without interfering with patient care, a refusal policy
cannot shift the consequences of professionals' refusals to patients.
Medical ethics place a duty on practitioners to place the patient's
interests above their own, but ethics alone do not ensure that practi-
tioners will set up systems to ensure that patients are not harmed by
refusal if there is a legal system that shifts the damages resulting from
such refusals away from the practitioner and onto the patient.
Medical professionals must take responsibility for their own moral
guideposts by accepting the burdens that result from such beliefs. A
system that keeps legal burdens, such as liability and professional
consequences, on professionals who breach their duties towards pa-
tients incentivizes practitioners to ensure that systems are in place to
protect the patient from harm as a prerequisite to the practitioner's
right to walk away from services to which he objects.
Part II describes the problems that result when practitioners place
their moral positions over the patient's welfare by refusing services
without ensuring that patient protections from harms resulting from
their refusals are in place. Part III describes bases for the professional's
duty to provide accurate and unbiased medical information, referrals,
and treatment in emergencies. Part IV discusses how current refusal
policy contravenes medical ethics by shifting the consequences of refusal
from practitioners to patients. Part V provides recommendations for
public policy on refusal that would provide maximum protection for
practitioners' right to act in accordance with their consciences without
abrogating their professional obligation to put the patient first.
I. THE PROBLEM WITH REFUSALS
Imagine your wife is nineteen weeks pregnant when her water
breaks. You rush her to the emergency room. The doctor comes out
and tells you that nothing can be done to save the baby. You ask how
AVE MARIA LAW REVIEW
your wife is doing. The doctor says that she will not be stable until
they remove the fetus, but the hospital's ethical rules prevent them
from doing so until there are no fetal heart tones. Instead, she will be
transferred to the intensive care unit and will receive blood trans-
fusions until the fetus dies in utero. Only then will she receive the
treatment she needs.1
Imagine your sister has been raped. She goes to a pharmacy for
emergency contraception, which is an FDA-approved contraceptive
that can be taken after unprotected sex.2 She can see it behind the
1. Description of this hypothetical incident is derived from facts described in NAT'L
HEALTH LAW PROGRAM, HEALTH CARE REFUSALS: UNDERMINING QUALITY CARE FOR WOMEN 47 (2010), http://www.healthlaw.org/images/stories/Health_Care_Refusals_Undermining_ Quality_Care_for_Women.pdf (describing a patient whose membranes ruptured and who be-came septic, but was denied an abortion by the hospital ethics committee because there was still a fetal heartbeat; she was in the intensive care unit for ten days, during which time she had "substantial internal bleeding, and developed pulmonary disease, resulting in lifetime oxy-gen dependency").
2. The process of becoming pregnant involves release of an ovum, fertilization of the
ovum by sperm, and implantation of the fertilized egg in the uterus. Press Release, Am. Cong. of Obstetricians & Gynecologists, Medical Groups Set the Record Straight on Emergency Contra-ception (May 4, 2004), http://www.acog.org/from_home/publications/press_releases/nr05- 04-04-3.cfm. The majority of scientific and medical groups define pregnancy as beginning with the implantation of a fertilized egg in the uterine wall. E.g. Dennies Varughese, Conscience
Misbranded!: Introducing the Performer v. Facilitator Model for Determining the Suitability of
Including Pharmacists Within Conscience Clause Legislation, 79 TEMP. L. REV. 649, 672–73 (2006). Emergency contraception (EC) pills prevent pregnancy after intercourse by interfering with at least one of these stages (in the current forms, primarily ovulation), unlike medical abortion, which is used to end pregnancy after a fertilized egg has implanted in a woman's uterus. Office of Population Research, Princeton Univ. & Assoc. of Reproductive Health Prof'ls, Emergency
Contraception: Emergency Contraceptives Are Not Abortion, http://ec.princeton.edu/questions/ ecabt.html (last visited Feb. 7, 2011). Levonorgestrel, a synthetic progestin, is the only EC approved by the FDA for over-the-counter distribution. See FDA, U.S. DEPT. OF HEALTH & HUMAN SERV., POSTMARKET DRUG SAFETY INFORMATION: PLAN B (.75MG LEVONORGESTREL) (2010), available
at http://www.fda.gov/drugs/drugsafety/postmarketdrugsafetyinformationforpatientsand providers/ucm109775.htm; Office of Population Research, Princeton Univ. & Assoc. of Re-productive Health Prof'ls, Emergency Contraception: Emergency Contraception OTC, http://ec. princeton.edu/questions/QA-OTC-access.html (last visited Feb. 7, 2011) (explaining that progestin-only EC pills, such as Plan B One-Step and Next Choice, are available over the counter for consumers 17 and older, while ulipristal acetate is sold by prescription only). Levonor-gestrel, currently marketed as Plan B One-Step and Next Choice, works primarily by preventing ovulation and may prevent fertilization, but there is no scientific evidence to support the idea that it can prevent implantation, and it is clear that it does not affect an implanted fertilized egg. CTR. FOR DRUG EVALUATION & RESEARCH, FDA, APPROVED LABELING FOR APPLICATION 21-045/S011, at 3 (2006) (labeling insert of application), available at http://www.accessdata. fda.gov/drugsatfda_docs/nda/2006/021045s011_Plan_B_PRNTLBL.pdf. ("Plan B works like a birth control pill to prevent pregnancy mainly by stopping the release of an egg from the ovary. It is possible that Plan B may also work by preventing fertilization of an egg (the uniting of sperm with the egg) or by preventing attachment (implantation) to the uterus (womb), which
Fall 2010] TOWARDS PATIENT-CENTERED CARE 145
counter, but the pharmacist refuses to give it to her because he thinks
it is immoral.3 She is distraught, yet she continues her search for the
medication in an effort to reduce her risk of becoming pregnant from
the traumatic act of violence.4
Imagine you are a newlywed, and you discover that you have
testicular cancer. You and your wife want kids, so you ask the doctor
how treatment is going to affect your fertility. He tells you not to
worry about it. You get the treatment without taking steps to store
your sperm, thinking that your doctor certainly would have told you
if the treatment had a chance of reducing your fertility. In reality,
your doctor is morally opposed to all assisted reproductive technologies
and thinks that discussing these procedures with you would make
him complicit in the sin.
Each of these situations is possible when providers are allowed
to place their religious and moral beliefs above medically accepted
standards of care and patients' needs.
usually occurs beginning seven days after release of an egg from the ovary. Plan B will not do anything to a fertilized egg already attached to the uterus. The pregnancy will continue."); see
also Sandra Reznik, "Plan B:" How It Works, HEALTH PROGRESS, Jan.–Feb. 2010, at 59, 61,
available at http://chausa.org/WorkArea/linkit.aspx?LinkIdentifier=id&ItemID=6159. The Ca-tholic Health Association (CHA) has acknowledged that traditional emergency contraception is not an abortifacient because scientific evidence does not support the claim that it prevents implantation of a fertilized egg. Reznik, supra, at 59, 61 ("[Plan B or] levonorgestrel acts to prevent pregnancy before, and only before, fertilization occurs . . [L]evonorgestrel prevents ovulation . . Some of the concerns about how Plan B works have been driven by the unfort-unate and inaccurate description on the package insert, which includes a statement that levonor-gestrel acts by preventing implantation. There are absolutely no data to support this statement, while there are plenty of data . . to support the conclusion that levonorgestrel acts only before fertilization has occurred."). Ulipristal acetate, approved in 2010 to be marketed as prescription-only Ella, is more effective than levonorgestrel because it can prevent the release of an ovum even after the hormone surge that triggers ovulation has begun; thus, its main mode of action is still preventing ovulation. WATSON PHARMA, INC., PRESCRIBING INFORMATION 5 (2010) (approved Aug. 13, 2010), available at http://www.accessdata.fda.gov/drugsatfda_docs/ label/2010/022474s000lbl.pdf. It is also possible that Ella inhibits implantation of a fertilized egg. Id. "No studies have been performed on the use of ulipristal acetate in pregnant women, but available data on inadvertent exposure of very early pregnancy to ulipristal acetate in clinical trials . . at the to-be-marketed dose for EC indicates that the product does not interrupt an established pregnancy." HRA PHARMA, BRIEFING MATERIALS FOR ADVISORY COMMITTEE FOR REPRODUCTIVE HEALTH DRUGS, FDA: ULIPRISTAL ACETATE 30 MG TABLET 84 (2010), available at http://www.fda.gov/downloads/AdvisoryCommittees/CommitteesMeetingMaterials/Drugs/ ReproductiveHealthDrugsAdvisoryCommittee/UCM215510.pdf.
3. Description of this hypothetical incident is based on widely reported facts described in
Varughese, supra note 2, at 650 (describing a news account of a rape victim denied emergency contraception by three pharmacists on duty).
AVE MARIA LAW REVIEW
[Major] health care provider organizations—including the American
College of Obstetricians and Gynecologists, the American Hospital
Association, and the American Public Health Association—have ex-
pressed concerns about the impact of refusals on patient care,5 [yet]
some providers still assert a right to deny patients medically appro-
priate health care services, information and referrals.6
While providers have a right to their moral beliefs, this right does
not allow health-care providers to violate their professional and legal
obligations to the patient. Policies on health-care provider refusals
should be carefully crafted to maximize the rights of individuals to
their beliefs without extending this "protection" so far that it prevents
patients from getting the medical care or information they need.
A. Who is Harmed?
There are three types of refusals: refusal to provide treatment,
refusal to provide information and refusal to provide referrals. Each
type of refusal can be undertaken by different types of providers.
Providers include individuals, such as doctors, nurses, and other
medical staff, as well as institutions, such as religiously-affiliated
hospitals.7 The problem of refusals affecting patient care extends
beyond hospitals and other institutions that actually provide health
care.8 "Like hospitals, managed care plans may also be religiously-
NAT'L WOMEN'S LAW CTR., WHEN HEALTH CARE PROVIDERS REFUSE: THE IMPACT ON
PATIENTS OF PROVIDERS' RELIGIOUS AND MORAL OBJECTIONS TO GIVE MEDICAL CARE, INFOR-MATION OR REFERRALS 1 (2009) (footnote added), http://www.nwlc.org/sites/default/files/ pdfs/April2009RefusalFactsheet.pdf; see also Farr A. Curlin et al., Religion, Conscience, and
Controversial Clinical Practices, 356 NEW ENG. J. MED. 593, 593 (2007) ("Many physicians do not consider themselves obligated to disclose information about or refer patients for legal but morally controversial medical procedures.").
7. Catholic hospitals have the broadest range of religious restrictions on medical practice
and are governed by the Ethical and Religious Directives for Catholic Health Care Services (hereinafter the Directives). U.S. CONF. OF CATHOLIC BISHOPS, ETHICAL AND RELIGIOUS DIREC-TIVES FOR CATHOLIC HEALTH CARE SERVICES (4th ed. 2001), available at http://www.usccb.org/ bishops/directives.shtml (generally prohibiting sterilizations, abortions, artificial reproductive technologies, and contraception).
NAT'L HEALTH LAW PROGRAM, supra note 1, at 6–7 (noting that reproductive health
and sexual activity related services have been restricted by broad expansion of the contingent of physicians, other health-care providers and large religiously-controlled nonprofit health-care corporations who refuse to provide services to which they have personal and religious objections).
Fall 2010] TOWARDS PATIENT-CENTERED CARE 147
affiliated, and exclude coverage for reproductive health services."9
Women have also been subject to refusals to sell them emergency
contraception and ordinary birth control in pharmacies.10
People often ask of those who are refused health-care services—
"Can't they just go somewhere else?" Unfortunately, the answer is of-
ten no, particularly when the refusing entity is an institutional actor,
such as a hospital or pharmacy, rather than an individual practitioner.
When professionals refuse to provide treatment, there may be nowhere
else in the patient's community where she can go or going elsewhere
may be financially out of reach.11 Furthermore, a patient who is re-
fused information may not know that she has been denied medically
desirable treatment options.12 A patient who is refused a referral may
be prevented by the refusal itself from going elsewhere for the service
if, for example, her managed care plan requires a physician referral.13
The consequences of refusals are particularly burdensome to marg-
inalized populations. Women are disproportionately burdened because
reproductive health services are the subject of the vast majority of re-
fusals. Low-income people, people of color, Lesbian/Gay/Bisexual/
Transgendered (LGBT) people, and people who live in areas with few
accessible providers also suffer disproportionately.14 A person in a
NAT'L WOMEN'S LAW CTR., supra note 6, at 2; see also NAT'L HEALTH LAW PROGRAM,
supra note 1, at 7 (noting that many hospitals are now controlled by organizations that place religious or moral restrictions on the services the hospitals may offer). 10.
Pharmacists' Rights at Front of New Debate: Because of Beliefs, Some Refuse
to Fill Birth Control Prescriptions, WASH. POST, Mar. 28, 2005, at A1.
11. See Letter from Tony Ogburn & Eve Espey, Chair & Vice Chair, Am. Coll. of Obste-
tricians & Gynecologists—N.M. Section, to Michael O. Leavitt, Sec'y, U.S. Dep't of Health & Human Servs. 2 (Sept. 24, 2008), available at http://www.regulations.gov/search/Regs/home. html#documentDetail?R=0900006480722c24 ("For patients without health insurance or access to transportation, [being forced by a refusal to seek care in another facility or another community] can mean no healthcare services at all.").
12. Letter from Georges C. Benjamin, Exec. Dir., Am. Pub. Health Ass'n, to Michael O. Lea-
vitt, Sec'y, U.S. Dep't of Health & Human Servs. 2 (Sept. 25, 2008), available at http://www. regulations.gov/search/Regs/home.html#documentDetail?R=0900006480723fce ("[P]atients might not even learn which services, information or referrals they may have been denied, elim-inating their right to fully informed consent, which involves a discussion on all medically recommended treatments and alternative treatment methods.").
Cal. Office of the Patient Advocate, What Is an HMO?, http://www.opa.ca.gov/
report_card/hmowhatis.aspx (last visited Feb. 7, 2011) ("If members [of HMOs] get services without a referral and approval they may have to pay for the service themselves.").
14. Letter from Tony Ogburn to Michael Leavitt, supra note 11, at 3 ("[T]he lowest income
women . . suffer the most" from refusal regulations that do "not take into account the needs and rights of patients."); Letter from Marcia D. Greenberger & Judy Waxman, Co-President & Vice President for Health & Reproductive Rights, Nat'l Women's Law Ctr., to Charles Johnson,
AVE MARIA LAW REVIEW
rural area may need to travel long distances in order to get needed
care; if the closest provider refuses, she may be left without an
alternative source of care.15 Even in urban areas, a rape survivor who
is refused emergency contraception may have to take public trans-
portation or hire a taxi to try to find a willing pharmacy late at night.
In the face of anxiety, embarrassment, or trauma, a woman may not
continue her search in the wake of multiple refusals.16 These refusals
have the greatest negative impact on low-income people who may not
have transportation, the job flexibility to take time off to seek needed
health care or who may not be able to afford an out-of-network pro-
vider or a second visit after a first visit ends in refusal.17
Many patients, especially those who are less educated or who
cannot afford second opinions, must trust and rely on their providers
to tell them about all of the medically appropriate treatment options
they might consider.18 But some doctors withhold information on
certain diagnoses, available diagnostic tests, and treatment options
due to their religious beliefs.19 Less educated patients are more likely
to be harmed by refusals to provide information because they may
not be aware that they have encountered a refusal at all. For example,
a study of California women shows that 72 percent of women with a
college diploma were aware of emergency contraception, compared to
only 48 percent with a high school diploma and 29 percent with less
than a high school diploma.20 Acting Sec'y, U.S. Dep't of Health & Human Servs. 3–6 (Apr. 9, 2009), available at http://www. nwlc.org/sites/default/files/pdfs/NWLC%20Rescission%20Comments%20FINAL.pdf.
generally FED. OFFICE OF RURAL HEALTH POL'Y, U.S. DEP'T OF HEALTH & HUMAN
SERVS., FACTS ABOUT . . RURAL PHYSICIANS (Sept. 1997), http://www.shepscenter.unc.edu/rural /pubs/finding_brief/FB53.pdf (noting the areas that are underserved by health-care profess-ionals in the United States). 16. Kristen Marttila Gast, Cold Comfort Pharmacy: Pharmacist Tort Liability for Con-
scientious Refusals to Dispense Emergency Contraception, 16 TEX. J. WOMEN & L. 149, 153 (2007)
17. See Susan Berke Fogel & Lourdes A. Rivera, Religious Beliefs and Healthcare Necessities:
Can They Coexist?, HUMAN RIGHTS, Spring 2003, at 8, 8–9, available at http://www.abanet. org/irr/hr/spring03/religiousbeliefs.html ("Restriction of services affects everyone, but low-income women are particularly vulnerable due to lack of resources to either pay out-of-pocket fees or to travel long distances to obtain services.").
18. See Diana G. Foster et al., Trends in Knowledge of Emergency Contraception Among
Women in California, 1999–2004, 17 WOMEN'S HEALTH ISSUES 22, 22 (2007) ("Foreign-born Hispanic women, women whose income falls below the poverty level, and women who did not complete high school" are least likely to know about emergency contraception). 19.
NAT'L WOMEN'S LAW CTR., HOW RELIGIOUS REFUSALS TO PROVIDE INFORMATION ABOUT
REPRODUCTIVE HEALTH SERVICES CAN VIOLATE PATIENTS' RIGHT TO INFORMED CONSENT 1–2 (2009), http://www.nwlc.org/sites/default/files/pdfs/InformedConsent09.pdf. 20.
supra note 18, at 24–25.
Fall 2010] TOWARDS PATIENT-CENTERED CARE 149
Inaccurate medical information undermines the practice of modern
medicine, which is based on a model that treats the patient as the
central decision maker and is dependent on a patient's confidence
that he or she is receiving evidence-based care and information.21 A
prior model, paternalism, which posited that the doctor should make
decisions on the patient's behalf, "is widely criticized for violating the
right of adults to self-determination."22 Because modern medicine
treats patients as participants in their own care, final decisions about
what treatment to undergo are left to them.23 If patients receive in-
accurate or incomplete information, their ability to make an optimal
medical decision is compromised.
B. What is the Harm?
Refusals subject women to serious physical, emotional, and finan-
cial consequences. They also damage public health efforts and violate
patients' rights. Refusals to provide information and referrals also
undermine the trust that patients place in their providers.
Refusals to provide information cause patients to lose control of
their health-care decisions, and can result in serious physical health
consequences.24 If a provider is opposed to family planning and refuses
to counsel a woman with a condition such as diabetes about her
increased risks during pregnancy and the benefits of delaying preg-
nancy until her condition is under control, she may be denied the
essential information she needs to reduce her risks of serious health
complications, including high blood pressure, kidney disease, nerve
NAT'L HEALTH LAW PROGRAM, supra note 1, at 12–13.
22. Curlin et al., supra note 6, at 599.
23. Some commentators on conscience in the religious context have asserted that not only
medical ethics, but also religious ethics dictate that the right of the patient to make medical decisions based on her own conscience must be accorded deference by providers. See, e.g., Sara Hutchinson, In Good Conscience? Examining the Abuse of Conscience Clauses in the U.S., 31 CONSCIENCE 35, 35–36 (2010) ("Catholic teaching requires due deference to the conscience of others in making decisions—meaning that healthcare providers must not dismiss the conscience of the person seeking care.")
NAT'L WOMEN'S LAW CTR., supra note 19, at 1–2; Am. Pub. Health Ass'n, Ensuring
that Individuals Are Able to Obtain Contraceptives at Pharmacies, APHA.ORG (Nov. 8, 2006), http://www.apha.org/advocacy/policy/policysearch/default.htm?id=1335 (explaining that access to contraceptives is essential for some women, for whom "pregnancy can entail great health risks and even life endangerment").
AVE MARIA LAW REVIEW
damage, heart disease, and blindness.25 Likewise, if a patient be-
lieves her doctor's statement that her inability to get pregnant is "all
in her head"—when in fact the doctor is opposed to giving her a re-
ferral to an infertility specialist—she may delay seeking time sensitive
treatment and lose her opportunity to bear biologically related children.
Refusals to provide treatment also impose serious health con-
sequences.26 The Ethical and Religious Directives for Catholic Health
Care Services (the Directives) govern the provision of care at Catholic-
affiliated hospitals. The Directive addressing abortion states:
Abortion (that is, the directly intended termination of pregnancy
before viability or the directly intended destruction of a viable fetus)
is never permitted. Every procedure whose sole immediate effect is
the termination of pregnancy before viability is an abortion, which,
in its moral context, includes the interval between conception and
implantation of the embryo.27
The United States Conference of Catholic Bishops, which authors the
Directives, interprets the Directive on abortion to mean that any abor-
tion that involves the direct removal of the fetus by a doctor is never
permissible for any reason.28 However, there is a separate Directive
25. Diabetes and Pregnancy, CTRS. FOR DISEASE CONTROL & PREVENTION (May 10, 2010),
http://www.cdc.gov/Features/DiabetesPregnancy/ (explaining that if a woman's diabetes cannot be controlled before and during pregnancy, it can cause or worsen problems such as "high blood pressure, kidney disease, nerve damage, heart disease, or blindness"); see also Alan L. Graber et. al, Planning for Sex, Marriage, Contraception, and Pregnancy, 1 DIABETES CARE 202, 203 (1978) ("The diabetic condition should be under good control in the nonpregnant state, since pregnancy will aggravate diabetes and make it harder to control."); Inge M. Evers et. al, Risk of
Complications of Pregnancy in Women with Type I Diabetes: Nationwide Prospective Study in
the Netherlands, 328 BRIT. MED. J. 915, 917 (2004), available at http://www.bmj.com/content/ 328/7445/915.abridgement.pdf (Even in a sample in which diabetes is generally well controlled, the risks of pregnancy complications were considerably higher than in the general population; however, "[t]he incidence of major congenital malformations was significantly lower in the planned pregnancies than in unplanned pregnancies."). 26.
NAT'L HEALTH LAW PROGRAM, supra note 1, at 12 ("Decisions to deny information and
services based on personal and religious beliefs rather than scientific evidence ultimately result in poor health outcomes for women."). 27.
U.S. CONF. OF CATHOLIC BISHOPS, ETHICAL AND RELIGIOUS DIRECTIVES FOR CATHOLIC
HEALTH CARE SERVICES 26 (5th ed. 2009), available at http://www.nccbuscc.org/meetings/ 2009Fall/docs/ERDs_5th_ed_091118_FINAL.pdf.
28. According to the Bishops, the Directives prohibit "direct abortion" under all circum-
stances. COMM. ON DOCTRINE, U.S. CONF. OF CATHOLIC BISHOPS, THE DISTINCTION BETWEEN DIRECT ABORTION AND LEGITIMATE MEDICAL PROCEDURES 2 (2010), http://usccb.org/doctrine/ direct-abortion-statement2010-06-23.pdf (explaining that a "direct abortion" is one in which "[i]t is the surgical instrument in the hands of the doctor that causes the child's death" and that such
Fall 2010] TOWARDS PATIENT-CENTERED CARE 151
regarding circumstances where a treatment that is not considered a
"direct abortion" would be permitted. Directive 47 states: "Operations,
treatments, and medications that have as their direct purpose the cure
of a proportionately serious pathological condition of a pregnant
woman are permitted when they cannot be safely postponed until the
unborn child is viable, even if they will result in the death of the
unborn child."29 Interpretations regarding whether an abortion is
considered a direct abortion and therefore prohibited under any
circumstance or an indirect abortion and therefore permitted under
some narrow circumstances has enormous implications for women's
ability to access the standard of care at Catholic-affiliated hospitals.
The potentially devastating health outcomes that sometimes flow
from refusal to perform "direct abortion" under any circumstances is
illustrated by a case in Phoenix, where the Diocese of Phoenix strip-
ped a Catholic hospital of its affiliation with the Church after the hos-
pital performed an abortion on a woman whose "risk of death was
nearly 100 percent" if she did not receive the abortion because the
fetus was "directly killed."30 The CHA supported the hospital's deci-
sion to allow the procedure, stating that it acted ethically under the
Directives by "saving the only life it was possible to save."31 While in an act "is never morally permissible. . no matter what the reason"). Directive 47 allows medical procedures that result in the removal of the fetus, but only if the removal of the fetus is not accomplished directly; the Directive would, for example, allow the removal of a pregnant woman's uterus if her uterus developed cancer and treatment could not be delayed until the fetus was viable. Id at 2–3. However, Directive 47 does not allow the removal of the fetus from the uterus "where the mother's health or even life is at risk during a pregnancy." Id. at 1, 3. Following the examples provided to their conclusion, if a pregnant woman's uterine cancer mass could be removed by surgery, saving her uterus and future fertility as well as her life, but an abortion would be required first to allow doctors access to her cancer mass, a woman in a facility following the Directives would not be offered that option. 29.
U.S. CONF. OF CATHOLIC BISHOPS, supra note 28. The Catholic Health Association, the
membership organization for Catholic-affiliated institutions, has opined that a procedure including membrane rupture and induced labor would be considered "indirect" abortion if the pregnant woman had a uterine infection and the drug used to induce labor was necessary to treat the uterine infection itself; in this case, the "drug helped cure the infection (a treatment that was directly intended) and brought on delivery of a previable fetus (an outcome that was not directly intended)." Sr. Jean deBlois & Fr. Kevin D. O'Rourke, Care for the Beginning of Life:
The Revised Ethical and Religious Directives Discuss Abortion, Contraception and Assisted
Reproduction, HEALTH PROGRESS, Sept.– Oct. 1995, at 36, 39. 30. Amanda Lee Myers, Ariz. Diocese Revokes Hospital's Status After Surgery, VALLEYNEWSLIVE.COM (Dec. 21, 2010 1:49P.M.), http://www.valleynewslive.com/Global/ story.asp?S=13721814.
31. Catholic Health Association Statement Regarding St. Joseph's Hospital and Medical
Center in Phoenix (Dec. 22, 2010), http://chausa.org/newsdetail.aspx?id=2147488971. The U.S. Conference of Catholic Bishops publicly disagreed with the hospital's position that the Direc-tives permit abortion where in the absence of an abortion both the woman and the fetus would
AVE MARIA LAW REVIEW
this case the hospital performed the procedure and suffered the
consequences from the Diocese, in other cases the Directives have
limited the medical treatment available in Catholic hospitals; one
study showed that Catholic hospitals refused to provide medically
necessary emergency treatment to women who were miscarrying be-
cause the doctors could still detect a fetal heartbeat.32
Ectopic pregnancies, which occur when the embryo implants in
the fallopian tube rather than the uterus, never result in live birth; if
left untreated, the woman risks fallopian tube rupture and infection,
which can be deadly. There are four treatment options for treating an
ectopic pregnancy: administering a medication to expel the embryo
from the fallopian tube (methotrexate), surgical removal of the em-
bryo from the fallopian tube (salpingostomy), surgical removal of the
fallopian tube where the embryo is embedded (salpingectomy) and
expectant management—monitoring the condition to see if it resolves
on its own.33 The Directive on abortion, which does not differentiate
between ectopic and intra-uterine pregnancy, has been interpreted by
some Catholic hospitals to allow only expectant management and
removal of the fallopian tube because removing the fallopian tube is
not a direct action against the embryo, while administering medication
to expel the embryo or removing the embryo itself would be "direct
abortion."34 A salpingectomy could reduce the woman's fertility, not survive. COMM. ON DOCTRINE, U.S. CONF. OF CATHOLIC BISHOPS, supra note 29, at 3 ("direct abortion is never permissible because a good end cannot justify an evil means"). 32. Lori R. Freedman et al., When There's a Heartbeat: Miscarriage Management in
Catholic-Owned Hospitals, 98 AM. J. PUB. HEALTH 1774, 1774 (2008) (documenting that a qualitative study showed some Catholic-affiliated hospitals refuse to evacuate the uterus of wo-men who are miscarrying if there is still a detectable fetal heartbeat).
33. Anne-Marie Lozeau & Beth Potter, Diagnosis and Management of Ectopic Pregnancy,
72 AM. FAM. PHYSICIAN 1707 (2005), available at http://www.aafp.org/afp/2005/1101/p1707.html. 34.
ANGEL M. FOSTER ET AL., IBIS REPRODUCTIVE HEALTH, ASSESSING HOSPITAL POLICIES &
PRACTICES REGARDING ECTOPIC PREGNANCY & MISCARRIAGE MANAGEMENT 5 (2010), available at http://nwlc.org/sites/default/files/pdfs/ibis_rh_-_nwlc_qualitative_study_report.pdf. See also William E. May, Arguments Against Salpingostomy and Methotrexate, in CATHOLIC HEALTH CARE ETHICS: A MANUAL FOR PRACTITIONERS 119–21 (arguing that methotrexate and salping-ostomy are incompatible with the Directives). While in practice some Catholic hospitals acting on their interpretations of the Directives have refused to provide methotrexate or removal of the embryo from the fallopian tube, other Catholic ethicists have disagreed with this inter-pretation of "direct abortion." NAT'L CATHOLIC BIOETHICS CTR., CATHOLIC HEALTH CARE ETHICS: A MANUAL FOR PRACTITIONERS 121–23, The Ethics of Treating Ectopic Pregnancy, Arguments in Favor of Salpingostomy 121–23. (Edward J. Furton et al. eds., 2d ed. 2009) (supporting the use of both tube-sparing surgery and methotrexate). The Catholic Health Asso-ciation has noted that there is a lack of clarity regarding what the Directives require and prohibit in ectopic pregnancy management. See Fr. Kevin D. O'Rourke, Applying the Directives: The
Ethical and Religious Directives Concerning Three Medical Situations Require Some Eluci-
Fall 2010] TOWARDS PATIENT-CENTERED CARE 153
where a treatment that would simply remove the embryo from the
fallopian tube, either by surgery or through use of medication, could
have saved her life with less negative effect on her future fertility.35
Medication to remove the embryonic tissue, the medically appropriate
option that could possibly preserve fertility in many cases, though
one that is often disallowed by the Directives, has the added benefit of
not exposing the woman to the risks of surgery.36
Restrictive interpretations of the Directives can force physicians
to refuse to admit women who are medically unstable, forcing these
patients to endanger their health by going elsewhere or staying and
receiving sub-standard treatment.37 One doctor recounted how a Cath-
olic hospital refused to admit his patient for an abortion, even though
she was having an inevitable miscarriage and delaying the removal of
the fetus put her at risk of serious infection.38 The hospital wanted
him to wait until she actually contracted an infection that would put
her life in danger:
dation, HEALTH PROGRESS, July–Aug. 1998, at 64, 65–66 (referring to the use of methotrexate, Fr. O'Rourke said "[I]t seems well within moral probity for the obstetrician to intend the removal of the trophoblast and to employ the means to fulfill the intention, even though that means the death of the fetus will result."). 35.
FOSTER ET AL., supra note 34, at 4; Mylene Yao & Togas Tulandi, Current Status of
Surgical and Nonsurgical Management of Ectopic Pregnancy, 67 FERTILITY & STERILITY 421 (1997) (intrauterine pregnancy rates are around 61% for patients who undergo salpingostomy and 54% for patients who take methotrexate but just 38.1% for patients who undergo partial or total salpingectomy).
FOSTER ET AL., supra note 34, at 15; Ramesh Raghavan, A Question of Faith, 297 J.
AM. MED. ASS'N 1412, 1412 (2007).
38. Tom C.W. Lin provides an account of this incident:
Kathleen Hutchins, a Medicaid patient of Manchester, New Hampshire, . . was denied an emergency termination of her fourteen-week pregnancy at Elliot Hospital when her amniotic sac broke prematurely. Elliot Hospital had previously merged with the only other hospital in Manchester, Catholic Medical Center. As a condition of the merger agreement, Elliot Hospital had agreed to ban abortions except to save a woman's life. Despite the warnings of Hutchins' physician, Dr. Wayne Goldner, that if the procedure was not performed she could face a lethal infection, administrators at Elliot Hospital told Dr. Goldner that he could not terminate Hutchins' pregnancy at Elliot Hospital unless her life was at immediate risk.
Ultimately, Dr. Goldner hired a cab to take Ms. Hutchins eighty miles to the nearest hospital that would treat her. Perhaps more troubling is the fact that most conscience clauses would protect the hospital from any liability under similar circumstances. Tom C.W. Lin, Treating an Unhealthy
Conscience: A Prescription for Medical Conscience Clauses, 31 VT. L. REV. 105, 130 (2006) (foot-notes omitted).
AVE MARIA LAW REVIEW
"I was told I could not admit her unless there was a risk to her
life," . . "They said, ‘Why don't you wait until she has an infection or
she gets a fever?' They were asking me to do something other than the
standard of care. They wanted me to put her health in jeopardy."39
Even when the patient is admitted, "[i]n terms of miscarriage treat-
ment, patients are often bleeding very heavily before a dilation and
curettage is allowed."40 Individual practitioners have also refused in
similar situations, which can endanger their patients. For example, a
nurse working in a nonsectarian hospital's labor and delivery section
refused to treat a pregnant patient with a ruptured membrane "which
the Hospital describe[d] as a life-threatening condition" and another
patient with "complete placenta previa—a condition in which the fe-
tus's placenta completely covers the mother's cervix," which was also
"life-threatening."41
Refusals to provide treatment extend beyond refusals to treat
conditions caused by reproductive health problems to independent
conditions that a doctor may object to treating because the woman
is pregnant. For example, an Obstetrician/Gynecologist refused to
remove a large mass from an Oklahoma woman's uterus because it
would endanger her pregnancy, despite the woman's desire to ter-
minate the pregnancy.42 The mass was shutting off the woman's
colon and bladder, but she was in a Catch-22; the doctor refused to
remove the mass as long as she was pregnant, but an abortion could
not be performed with the mass in place.43 By the time the woman
found a doctor who would remove the mass, he had to remove her
uterus, which would have been unnecessary had the surgery been
performed earlier.44
39. Sabrina Rubin Erdely, Doctors' Beliefs Can Hinder Patient Care, MSNBC.COM ( June 22,
2007, 2:26 PM) (quoting Dr. Goldner), http://www.msnbc.com/id/19190916. 40.
FOSTER ET AL., supra note 34, at 13 (discussing Dr. Y's experiences at a Catholic hospital
41. Shelton v. Univ. of Med. & Dentistry of N.J., 223 F.3d 220, 222–23 & n.3 (3d Cir. 2000).
The court ruled that the hospital offered a "reasonable accommodation" to transfer the nurse to a different ward when she refused to treat certain pregnancy complications on the grounds that the treatment, in her view, amounted to an abortion. Id. at 226. The nurse was fired after she refused the transfer. Id. at 223 –24. The court wrote "we believe public trust and confidence requires that a public hospital's health care practitioners—with professional ethical obligations to care for the sick and injured—will provide treatment in time of emergency." Id. at 228. 42.
NAT'L HEALTH PROGRAM, supra note 1, at 7.
Fall 2010] TOWARDS PATIENT-CENTERED CARE 155
Refusals, misinformation and resulting physical harms may in-
flict emotional trauma. Many refusals take place in a context already
fraught with emotion, such as following sexual assault or during preg-
nancy complications.45 A woman experiencing an ectopic pregnancy or
miscarriage likely is already saddened by the loss of her pregnancy.46
Refusals imply an outsider's judgment that these women are doing
something wrong and invoke shame during a fragile time.
Rape is traumatizing because it destroys the sense of control that
a woman has over her body.47 The experience of having another per-
son assert control over an intimate bodily function is a dissociative
one that deeply affects a woman's sense of self. Women experience
rape as dehumanizing because it demonstrates another person's lack
of regard for her as an equal human being entitled to make her own
moral decisions. A central tenet of rape treatment, counseling and
recovery is that a woman's humanity and moral value must be re-
flected back to her by the people around her who do this by listening
to her decision-making process and respecting her decisions. For this
reason, rape crisis counselors are trained to provide non-directive
counseling. For example, a crisis counselor will not recommend that a
woman report her rape to law enforcement; instead, she will offer the
options of reporting or not reporting, will ask open-ended questions
to help the survivor consider her options, and will respect the wo-
man's decision even if it is not the one the counselor would have
made. Refusals to provide medical information to a rape victim
traumatize her again by substituting someone else's decision about
what should happen to her body and bypassing her moral decision
making authority completely in the same way that rape forces an
outsider's decision on the woman's body without the involvement of
Susan Berke Fogel & Lourdes A. Rivera, Saving Roe is Not Enough: When Religion
Controls Healthcare, 31 FORDHAM URB. L.J. 725, 735–36 (2004) (discussing abortions done in hospitals, which are therefore more likely to be subject to refusals, as occurring often with women who have just been raped, or who are medically fragile, as well as further into their pregnancies; for example, a woman might need a hospital abortion if her fetus is anencephalic, meaning that it does not have a cranium).
46. Early Pregnancy Loss: Miscarriage and Molar Pregnancy, AM. CONG. OF OBSTETRICIANS
& GYNECOLOGISTS (2002), http://www.acog.org/publications/patient_education/bp090.cfm ("For many women, miscarriage . . results in feelings of loss and grief."). 47.
Winters, Violence Against Women, in OUR BODIES, OURSELVES FOR THE NEW
CENTURY 158, 167 (1998), available at http://www.feminist.com/resources/ourbodies/viol_ sa.html (describing loss of control and powerlessness experienced by many rape survivors, noting that "healing can occur when you begin to regain a sense of power").
AVE MARIA LAW REVIEW
her decision making capacity, making her feel powerless.48 It is espe-
cially important that a rape survivor's moral autonomy be respected
because it empowers her to make her own decisions regarding her
body and shows her that other people respect her moral agency and
On top of the profound feeling of loss of power that many rape
survivors experience, a rape survivor may also be worried that she
will become pregnant.49 Refusals to provide information regarding
emergency contraception and emergency contraception itself increase
the chance that this fear will be realized.50 In order for rape survivors
to decide whether or not to use emergency contraception, their doctors
must provide them with information about it; "While nonprescription
availability [of traditional emergency contraception] makes adult
women less dependent on a physician's prescription than in years
past, studies repeatedly show that some women do not know about
EC, and even well-informed patients still rely on their physician's
advice."51 Individual practitioners who refuse to administer emer-
gency contraception themselves should nonetheless ensure that the
woman receives both information about emergency contraception and
the treatment itself through another practitioner at the same location
because if she is refused emergency contraception, a rape survivor
may not feel comfortable asking someone else at the hospital for
treatment, may feel too humiliated to ask a friend for transportation
to a willing provider, or may be afraid to walk to a pharmacy.
3. Financial Harms
Refusals reduce efficiency in health care delivery for low- and high-
income people alike.52 But the additional costs imposed on patients
48. See Erdely, supra note 39 ("I felt victimized all over again. First the rape, and then the
doctor making me feel powerless.") (quoting woman who was refused emergency contraception during her examination after being raped).
49. See Pregnancy, RAPE, ABUSE & INCEST NAT'L NETWORK (2009), http://rainn.org/get-
50. See Varughese, supra note 2, at 654 ("Emergency contraception can prevent preg-
nancy by [a variety of methods] . . [It] does not cause an abortion and, unlike abortifacients such as RU-486, is not effective once the fertilized egg implants in the uterine wall establish-ing pregnancy.").
51. Ryan E. Lawrence et al., Obstetrician-Gynecologist Physicians' Beliefs About Emergency
Contraception: A National Survey, 82 CONTRACEPTION 324, 329 (2010).
52. See FOSTER ET AL., supra note 34, at 12 (discussing a physician who reported "that a
primary difference between" practicing in a Catholic versus a secular setting is that one "must be ‘100% sure that the pregnancy isn't viable'" before performing a uterine evacuation, which
Fall 2010] TOWARDS PATIENT-CENTERED CARE 157
may mean that low-income people are denied access altogether. Re-
fusals impose additional costs because of insurance limitations. If a
woman's insurance covers only one visit to her gynecologist per year,
a common provision, her doctor's refusal to counsel her about family
planning, write a prescription for oral contraceptives, or provide such
services as intra-uterine device (IUD) insertion or diaphragm fitting
means that she will have to pay out of her own pocket to see another
gynecologist in order to get the services for which she should be
insured. A woman who is raped may not be able to afford emergency
contraception at a pharmacy, while her insurance would cover it if it
were administered at a hospital. All of the in-network hospitals may
refuse to provide certain services, forcing a woman to shoulder an
unaffordable cost-sharing burden by going to an out-of-network hos-
pital.53 Insurance providers themselves may include religious refusals.
Some states automatically enroll Medicaid beneficiaries into reli-
giously affiliated managed care plans that do not provide family
planning services. The beneficiary may be barred from seeing another
doctor for a certain period of time, or may face administrative diffi-
culties in switching managed care plans so that she can get the care
In addition to insurance and access issues, refusals can impose
additional costs for treatment.54 Two examples are miscarriage man-
agement and tubal ligation. "With respect to the management of mis-
carriages, a number of [physicians in Catholic hospitals] reported
having to order additional tests and/or perform diagnostic surgery in
order to definitively ascertain that a pregnancy was not viable."55
Despite the fact that a woman was having a miscarriage, the doctors
had to perform medically unnecessary tests before they could treat
her miscarriage, increasing the likelihood of negative health outcomes
for the woman as well as increasing the costs of the procedures.
Another example of unnecessary duplication of services occurs when
hospitals and individuals refuse to provide tubal ligation services to
women who are in the hospital to give birth or undergo cesareans. she noted "often requires additional paperwork and clinical tests including serial ßhCGs and/or additional ultrasounds," and, "given that ultrasonography is often inconclusive, physicians are often unclear as to what their options are [under the Catholic hospital's requirements]").
e.g., Laura Parker, Case Involves a Collision of Rights: Calif. Doctors Accused of
Using Faith to Violate Law Against Anti-Gay Bias, USA TODAY, Aug. 3, 2007, at 3A (relating the story of Guadalupe Benitez, a lesbian who was forced outside of her insurance network coverage after fertility clinic doctors refused to treat her on the basis of their religious beliefs). 54.
NAT'L WOMEN'S LAW CTR., supra note 6, at 5.
FOSTER ET AL., supra note 34, at 20.
AVE MARIA LAW REVIEW
Postpartum sterilization, which does not require additional hospital-
ization, and when performed with cesarean avoids an additional
surgery event and additional anesthesia, is often more convenient,
costs less, and is safer for the patient than having a sterilization per-
4. Harms to Public Health
Refusals to provide information or treatment are harmful to pu-
blic health efforts.57 "In an effort to circumvent a hospital or other
institution's religiously based opposition to contraception, some doc-
tors may falsely indicate that a patient needs contraception for a
medical reason, such as endometriosis or an irregular menstrual cycle.
However, this practice ultimately can harm the patient in the long
run" because this diagnosis will be in her medical records and future
insurers and doctors will believe that she has a preexisting medical
condition where none exists.58
Refusals may result in increased rates of unintended pregnancy.
Almost half of all pregnancies in the United States are unintended
and there has been a growing concentration of such pregnancies
among less educated and low-income women.59 Together, this may
indicate a need for greater public understanding of reproduction and
birth control.60 Proactive medical provider counseling on family plan-
ning can reduce unintended pregnancy.61 Conversely, refusals with-
out ensuring that patients are provided family planning counseling
services through another provider leaves an information gap because
56. See Keri Tonn, Note, Fraud on Your Conscience: Refusal to Offer Postpartum
Sterilization and Its Consequences, 11 MICH. ST. U. J. MED. & L. 203, 203 (2007). 57.
NAT'L WOMEN'S LAW CTR., supra note 6, at 5 – 6.
59. Lawrence B. Finer & Stanley K. Henshaw, Disparities in Rates of Unintended
Pregnancy in the United States, 1994 and 2001, 38 PERSPECTIVES ON SEXUAL & REPRODUCTIVE HEALTH 90, 90 (2006), available at http://www.guttmacher.org/pubs/psrh/full/3809006.pdf. 60.
KELLEEN KAYE ET AL., THE NAT'L CAMPAIGN TO PREVENT TEEN & UNPLANNED
PREGNANCY, THE FOG ZONE: HOW MISPERCEPTIONS, MAGICAL THINKING, AND AMBIVALENCE PUT YOUNG ADULTS AT RISK FOR UNPLANNED PREGNANCY 35–51 (2009) (discussing study findings that lack of knowledge about contraceptive methods, overestimation of the side effects of contra-ceptives, misinformation about pregnancy and contraception, and disbelief that contraception is effective are contributing factors to unplanned pregnancy).
61. Id. at 12 ("[T]he health care system can do more to help unmarried young adults plan
and prevent pregnancy by . . [e]nsuring that providers who care for young adults are well trained in family planning, aware of the full range of contraceptive methods now available, . . comfortable providing them to young adults[, and by e]ncouraging providers to do more counseling about pregnancy planning and prevention.").
Fall 2010] TOWARDS PATIENT-CENTERED CARE 159
"[y]oung adults overwhelmingly say that their most trusted source of
information about contraception is a medical provider."62 Without
medical professional involvement, patients may not have sufficient
information to know that birth control is effective,63 to choose be-
tween methods,64 or to use the chosen method effectively, and will not
be able to obtain the most effective methods, which currently require
prescriptions or practitioner insertion.65
Refusals also result in higher rates of sexually transmitted infec-
tions (STIs). Physicians, in primary care and wellness visits as well as
more specialized sexual health visits, play a major role in reducing the
spread of STIs, including HIV and other STIs that cause long-lasting
physical effects, such as infertility, by providing risk avoidance coun-
seling to uninfected and infected patients. A review of studies of HIV
interventions for people living with HIV found that the interventions
which significantly reduced sexual risk behaviors included "deli-
ver[y] by health-care providers or counsellors" and "deliver[y] in
settings where [people living with HIV] receive routine services or
medical care."66 Similarly, previous review of scientific studies has
shown that interventions in health-care settings also reduce risk be-
haviors among uninfected individuals.67 Hospitals or health-care
providers that refuse to counsel sexually active patients on the use of
at 9 ("Many unmarried young adults, both men and women, simply don't believe
that contraception is very effective. For example, 42% of men and 40% of women believe that the chance of getting pregnant within a year while using the birth control pill is 50% or greater (despite research suggesting that the pill is typically 92% effective)."(emphasis omitted)).
64. Id. at 8 (stating that while only 30% of unmarried young adults say they know "little or
nothing " about condoms, "63% say they know little or nothing about birth control pills" and "56% say they have not heard of the birth control implant.").
65. The most effective forms of contraception are only available through contact with
medical professionals; over-the-counter barrier methods are less effective than birth control pills, and intrauterine devices and birth control implants, which require insertion and removal by medical professionals, are more effective than birth control pills. E.g., OFFICE ON WOMEN'S HEALTH, U.S. DEP'T OF HEALTH & HUMAN SERVS., FREQUENTLY ASKED QUESTIONS: BIRTH CONTROL METHODS 7–10 (2009), http://www.womenshealth.gov/faq/birth-control-methods.pdf.
66. Nicole Crepaz et al., Do Prevention Interventions Reduce HIV Risk Behaviours Among
People Living with HIV? A Meta-Analytic Review of Controlled Trials, 20 AIDS 143, 143 (2006),
67. See, e.g., Mary Spink Neumann et al., Review and Meta-Analysis of HIV Prevention
Intervention Research for Heterosexual Adult Populations in the United States. 30 J. ACQUIRED IMMUNE DEFICIENCY SYNDROMES S106, S110 (2002), available at http://journals.lww.com/jaids/ pages/articleviewer.aspx?year=2002&issue=07011&article=00010&type=fulltext (discussing inter-ventions found to be successful at reducing sexual risk behaviors among uninfected people and noting that "interventions were conducted most frequently in health care settings").
AVE MARIA LAW REVIEW
condoms to prevent the sexual transmission of HIV or other STIs
contribute to higher rates of these infections by missing a major
opportunity to counsel on risk avoidance.
Refusals reinforce and perpetuate the idea that medical profess-
ionals are morally judging the behaviors of their patients. Research
shows that when patients are afraid of moral judgment, they are less
forthcoming about their health needs.68 Actually experiencing a re-
fusal to provide treatment may make a patient feel guilty, ashamed,
alienated from the health-care system, and fearful of being judged by
other providers.69 The more stigmas a person encounters from the
health provider community, the more opportunities are missed to
ensure adherence to treatment and prevention of negative public
health outcomes.70 A patient who has had a bad experience may avoid
contact with the health-care system entirely, including use of pre-
ventive care, until his or her condition becomes more serious, reducing
the chances of the patient recovering and contributing to greater
health-care costs. A patient may delay seeking medical attention until
an illness becomes unbearable enough to force him or her to go to one
of our nation's already overburdened emergency rooms, losing opp-
ortunities for early treatment and education on preventing further
spread in the community.
5. Violation of Patient Rights
Under the informed consent doctrine, patients have a right to be
given the full range of treatment options for their condition and told
the risks and benefits of each alternative, as well as the risks and
68. E.g., Stigma, Information Gaps Contribute to Silence on Sexual Health Matters;
National Survey Finds Many Women Not Discussing HIV, Other Sexually Transmitted Diseases
with Providers or Partners, ASCRIBE NEWSWIRE (June 17, 2003), http://newswire.ascribe.org/cgi-bin/behold.pl?ascribeid=20030616.155710&time=21%2002%20PDT&yeaer=2003&public=0 (noting that, according to a national survey, "[a]pproximately half of women, ages 18 to 49, report never having discussed . . STDs[] with a health care provider," and one of the most common reasons for forgoing discussion is "embarrassment or concern about being judged").
e.g., Erdely, supra note 39 (reporting that a patient refused emergency contraception
at a rape crisis hospital visit "remained haunted by the ER doctor's refusal—so profoundly, she [did not] see a gynecologist in the two and a half years since," and that she hadn't "gotten the nerve up to go, for fear of being judged again").
70. See Shalini Bharat & Vaishali Sharma Mahendra, Meeting the Sexual and Reproductive
Health Needs of People Living with HIV: Challenges for Health Care Providers, 15 REPROD. HEALTH MATTERS 93, 93 (2007) ("Supportive and knowledgeable providers are crucial for helping HIV-positive people seek and adhere to treatment, prevent sexually transmitted infec-tions, unintended pregnancies and vertical transmission of HIV and support positive living free from stigma and discrimination.").
Fall 2010] TOWARDS PATIENT-CENTERED CARE 161
benefits of abstaining from treatment.71 All fifty states and the District
of Columbia recognize physician liability based on lack of informed
consent.72 The doctrine of informed consent is generally applicable to
professionally-provided medical care of all specialties and exists in
large part to protect the patient's right to be his own decision-maker.73
Under the generally applicable standards of informed consent, a hos-
pital or provider who refuses to discuss treatment options or their
effects with a terminally ill patient violates the patient's rights to
informed consent to accept or refuse treatment.74 Similarly, a pro-
vider who leaves a patient unaware of available treatments or gives
her medically inaccurate information violates her right to informed
consent. For example, an ultrasound technician or doctor who refuses
to reveal fetal anomalies or an oncologist who refuses to discuss gam-
ete preservation before radiation treatments that will compromise
fertility violate the patient's right to informed consent.75 However,
under federal law and the laws of some states, the well established
right of patients to informed consent has been subject to carved out
exceptions, whereby the right to informed consent has been over-
ridden by statutes that allow certain people and institutions to opt-out
of compliance with these otherwise generally applicable laws (dis-
cussed further, infra Part III.B.).76
C. How Common Are Refusals and How Often Are Patients Harmed?
While there are many cases on record, the true scope of the problem
is both unknown and unknowable. "Religious hospitals represent
approximately 13% of all US community-based hospitals and pro-
71. Suzanne K. Ketler, Note, The Rebirth of Informed Consent: A Cultural Analysis of the
Informed Consent Doctrine After Schreiber v. Physicians Insurance Co. of Wisconsin, 95 NW. U. L. REV. 1029, 1037 (2001); Peter H. Schuck, Rethinking Informed Consent, 103 YALE L.J. 899, 901 (1994) (contract based conception of "individual autonomy" survives in the public health contexts of "mandated disclosures for patients whose care is financed under federal programs, and other statutorily required disclosures") (footnote omitted).
72. Jon F. Merz, On a Decision-Making Paradigm of Medical Informed Consent, 14 J.
LEGAL MED. 231, 231 (1993); see also NAT'L WOMEN'S LAW CTR., supra note 19, at 1 (noting that "most states include the failure . . to give informed consent in their medical malpractice laws"). 73.
supra note 72, at 231–32.
74. See Cruzan v. Dir., Mo. Dep't of Health, 497 U.S. 261, 269 (1990) ("The informed
consent doctrine has become firmly entrenched in American tort law."); id. at 277 ("[T]he common-law doctrine of informed consent is viewed as generally encompassing the right of a competent individual to refuse medical treatment.").
NAT'L WOMEN'S LAW CTR., supra note 19, at 2.
76. Fogel & Rivera, supra note 45, at 727.
AVE MARIA LAW REVIEW
vide nearly 20% of hospital beds," and many prohibit "certain end-
of-life" and reproductive health treatments.77 Based on the percentage
of physicians who "do not believe they are obligated to . . provide
referrals" when a patient requests a treatment the physician finds
morally objectionable, "29% of patients—or nearly 100 million Ameri-
cans" may have physicians who would refuse to refer for certain
procedures.78 "Advocates on both sides say the refusals appear to be
spreading, often surfacing only in the rare instances when women
file complaints."79
Complaints regarding institutional or individual refusals are "rare"
for many reasons, including that people who have been refused do
not know that they have experienced a refusal, because they are not
aware that such a refusal is unethical or illegal and may have a rem-
edy, or because they have privacy concerns. Because some providers
refuse to give information, some patients will never know that they
have experienced a different standard of care because of their doctor's
religious beliefs.80 Where the institution, such as the hospital, initiates
the refusals, even the physicians may not be aware that the limitations
on their practices are the result of a religious refusal. For example,
some Catholic hospitals do not make methotrexate, the nonsurgical
treatment for ectopic pregnancy, available within their institutions,
and "[a]lthough physicians from all institution types described metho-
trexate as their preferred line of treatment, it appears that some
physicians in Catholic hospitals are not directly associating the lack of
availability of methotrexate as a policy governed by the Directives."81
Even if she is refused treatment, a patient may not be aware that
she has experienced a refusal based on a nonmedical reason. For
example, a woman who was denied a dilation and curettage procedure
at a hospital after a sonogram showed that her baby was stillborn was
unaware that the denial was due to the hospital's religious affiliation
and not just standard practice for her condition. Likewise, a patient
may be transferred from a hospital emergency room that refuses to
77. Debra B. Stulberg et al., Religious Hospitals and Primary Care Physicians: Conflicts
over Policies for Patient Care, 25 J. GEN. INTERNAL MED. 725, 725 (2010). Over 40% of physician respondents in this study reported having taken care of patients in a religious-affiliated institution.
78. Curlin et al., supra note 6, at 597.
supra note 39 ("In many cases, women don't even know a doctor is with-
holding treatment."). 81.
FOSTER ET AL., supra note 34, at 19.
Fall 2010] TOWARDS PATIENT-CENTERED CARE 163
provide ectopic pregnancy treatment, and may never know the reason
for the refusal-based transfer. Similarly, some pharmacists will sim-
ply say that a drug is out of stock in order to avoid a confrontation.82
Because these women are unaware that they have experienced a reli-
gious refusal, they may never report their experiences.83
Even a patient who is aware that she has been refused treatment
based on providers' personal beliefs may not know that her rights
may have been violated, that there is anything she can do about it,
or who to call, and may therefore never report the refusal to a non-
profit organization, enforcement agency, or media outlet.84 Some
patients also do not want to incur the time, effort or possible expense
involved in filing a complaint. Still others do not complain about re-
fusals because of shame or embarrassment regarding the private nature
of the services sought, reluctance to open themselves to the possibility
of having to share sexual details publicly, or unwillingness to relive
traumatic experience such as a rape or miscarriage.85 Because patients
do not know that they have been subject to religious refusals or do
know but face disincentives to make reports, such as perceived
ineffectiveness, feeling of powerlessness over the medical establish-
ment, or concerns over privacy, refusal incidents are likely under-
counted substantially.
II. ORIGINS OF THE PROVIDER'S DUTY
Providers have a duty to provide informed consent, which con-
sists of providing sufficient information on all of the options which
(depending on the jurisdiction) either fit within the standard of care
e.g., Keren Rivas, Many Local Pharmacists Refuse to Fill Prescriptions for Emer-
gency Contraceptive, TIMES NEWS (Burlington, N.C.), Apr. 30, 2005; see also Complaint at 1–2, Brown, No. 200610078 (Ill. Dep't of Fin. & Prof'l Regulation Mar. 27, 2006), available at http://www.idfpr.com/newsrls/032706BrownOrder.pdf (alleging pharmacist lied when he said the pharmacy carried "Plan B" in the store).
83. See NAT'L WOMEN'S LAW CTR., NATIONAL WOMEN'S LAW CENTER COMMENTS ON
"NOTICE OF RIGHTS REGARDING THE DISPENSING OF CONTRACEPTIVES" 3–4 (2006), available at http://www.nwlc.org/sites/default/files/pdfs/TestimonyNoticeRule052406.pdf.
id. at 3 ("A woman subjected to a pharmacy refusal who is unaware of her rights
under the existing rule might leave the pharmacy without a necessary contraceptive drug or the resources she needs to find it elsewhere.").
85. See Erdely, supra note 39 (reporting that patients denied treatment by physicians
rarely complain because "the situation tends to feel so humiliatingly personal;" quoting Lori Boyer, a rape patient who was denied emergency contraception and did not come forward until a newspaper reported on the same doctor because he refused to provide another rape survivor with emergency contraception, "The whole situation was traumatizing and embarrassing, and I just wanted to put it behind me.").
AVE MARIA LAW REVIEW
or would be considered material to a reasonable patient's decision, as
well as a duty to obtain consent for all treatments actually performed.
This duty is based on professional ethical standards, many of which
have been incorporated into law by statute, regulation, and common
law. For example, states license health-care practitioners, bringing
such practitioners under the purview of laws designed to protect
public health and patient welfare and subjecting them to professional
discipline for violations of their duties. Other state statutes impose
criminal penalties on medical providers for failure to conform to specific
duties. Finally, informed consent and the standard of care are enforced
as civil duties arising under fiduciary duty and malpractice law.
A. Duty in Licensing
Medical professionals, including doctors, nurses and pharmacists,
are licensed by states. The license to practice medicine or pharmacy is
a privilege granted by the state in order to promote the public interest
in enforcing the professional standard that the patients' interests will
be paramount.86 The privilege to practice medicine comes with a duty
to serve and advance the state's interest in public health.87 Many
states govern medical providers' licenses based on ethical criteria set
by providers' professional organizations, which are often incorporated
by reference into state licensing statutes and regulations. Many of
these provisions limit refusals based on nonmedical considerations.
Many regulations limiting refusals are aimed at pharmacists be-
cause pharmacists traditionally have a duty to dispense prescribed
medication and are traditionally strongly discouraged from inter-
vening in the doctor-patient relationship. Many states' regulations
mandate transfer of prescriptions at the request of the patient, and
explicitly state that refusal to transfer by a pharmacy or pharmacist
constitutes unprofessional conduct or another violation of the state's
pharmacy rules and regulations.88 South Carolina has codified the
86. E.g., Robert S. Crausman, About the Board, BD. OF MED. LICENSURE & DISCIPLINE, R.I.
DEP'T OF HEALTH, http://www.health.ri.gov/hsr/bmld/ (last visited Feb. 7, 2011) ("Upon entering the profession we all pledge to uphold a high standard of professional behavior that selflessly places our patients' interests above our own. So extraordinary is this role and so ne-cessary is this commitment, that every state operates a governmental agency to monitor and enforce the professional conduct of physicians.").
e.g., Am. Pub. Health Ass'n, supra note 24 ("The practice of pharmacy is regulated
by each state for the purpose of protecting public health.").
e.g., MINN. R. 6800.3120 Subp. 9 (2009) ("The board shall consider it evidence of
unprofessional conduct for a pharmacist to refuse to provide a transfer of original prescription
Fall 2010] TOWARDS PATIENT-CENTERED CARE 165
American Pharmaceutical Association's Code of Ethics, discussed infra,
giving it the force of law.89 North Dakota has adopted the National
Association of Boards of Pharmacy's Model "Pharmacy Patient's Bill
of Rights" as law.90 Pharmacists must provide care consistent with the
patient's right "[t]o have the pharmacist serve as one of the patient's
advocates for appropriate drug therapy and to make reasonable efforts
to recommend alternative choices in cooperation with the patient's
physician" and "[t]o have the patient's prescriptions dispensed and
pharmacy services provided at a pharmacy of the patient's choice in an
atmosphere that allows for confidential communication."91
State pharmacy boards in Delaware, New York, North Carolina,
Oregon, and Texas have issued policy statements supporting patients'
right to receive their medications and clarifying that obstruction or
harassment of patients by pharmacists are inappropriate and, in some
instances, may give rise to discipline under existing laws and regula-
tions.92 Many states also require pharmacists to dispense medications
without obstruction or delay and provide patients with options if their
medication is out of stock.93 Disciplinary actions against pharmacists
information to another pharmacist who is acting on behalf of a patient and who is making a legal request for this information under this part."); OHIO ADMIN. CODE 4729-5-24(D)(2) (2010) ("No pharmacy shall refuse to transfer information about a previously dispensed prescription to another pharmacy when requested by the patient. Prescription information shall be transferred in accordance with this rule as soon as possible in order to assure that the patient's drug therapy is not interrupted."); 22 TEX. ADMIN. CODE § 291.34(d)(5) (2010) ("A pharmacist or pharmacist intern may not refuse to transfer original prescription information to another pharmacist or pharmacist intern who is acting on behalf of a patient and who is making a request for this information as specified in paragraph (4) of this subsection."). 89.
S.C. CODE ANN. § 40-43-86(W) (2009) (codifying the American Pharmaceutical Assoc-
iation's Code of Ethics for pharmacists). 90.
N.D. ADMIN. CODE 61-04-07-01 (2010).
92. Considering Moral and Ethical Objections, DSBP NEWS (Del. State Bd. of Pharmacy,
Dover, Del.,) Mar. 2006, at 4; Letter from Lawrence H. Mokhiber, Exec. Sec'y, N.Y. State Bd. of Pharmacy, to Supervising Pharmacists (Nov. 18, 2005), available at http://www.op.nysed. gov/prof/pharm/pharmconscienceguideline.htm; Pharmacist FAQs: Frequently Asked
Questions for Pharmacists on Conscience Clause, N.C. BD. OF PHARMACY (Apr. 2005), http:// www.ncbop.org/faqs/Pharmacist/faq_ConscienceClause.htm Position Statement: Considering
Moral and Ethical Objections, OR. BD. OF PHARMACY (June 7, 2006), available at http://www. oregon.gov/Pharmacy/M_and_E_Objections_6-06.pdf; TEX. STATE BD. OF PHARM., Plan B, http://www.tsbp.state.tx.us/planb.htm (last visited Feb. 7, 2011).
93. E.g., ILL. ADMIN. CODE tit. 68, § 1330.500(e) (2010). NEV. ADMIN. CODE § 639.753 (2010)
(Nevada pharmacists can only decline to fill prescriptions for professional reasons); see also
Pharmacy Asked to Withhold Judgment, LASVEGASSUN.COM (May 6, 2006), http:// www. lasvegassun.com/news/2006/may/06/pharmacy-asked-to-withhold-judgment/ (refusals based on moral or personal beliefs could result in discipline from the state).
AVE MARIA LAW REVIEW
for refusals to fill and transfer prescriptions have been undertaken
because these refusals constitute a departure from the professional
obligation to adhere to the standard of care.94
State regulations of professionals also outline the duty to provide
care for other health professionals. In New York, the rules applicable
to all licensed medical professionals, including pharmacists, define
"[a]bandoning or neglecting a patient under and in need of immediate
professional care, without making reasonable arrangements for the
continuation of such care . . " as "professional misconduct."95 Sim-
ilarly, in the District of Columbia the statute applicable to licensed
medical professionals defines abandoning a patient as "termination,
without adequate notice, of the professional relationship between a
health care provider and a patient or client at a time when the patient
or client is in need of further emergency care."96 Similarly, informed
consent requirements are defined by statute in most states, and are
based on common law in others.
These licensing laws, and laws like them in other states, are
designed to ensure that the focus of professionals is on providing
seamless care to patients. The personal, unscientific beliefs of pro-
fessionals do not generally allow them to breach the standard of care,
but they may refuse to provide any service so long as the refusal does
not conflict with the professional duty to ensure the patient's rights to
informed consent or to access treatment that conforms to professional
standards of care. However, in some states laws governing refusals
have altered this general rule so that professionals can be exempted
from the duty to provide the standard of care based on personal
ethical beliefs. Nonetheless, professionals have ethical obligations not
to breach these standards.
94. E.g., JODY FEDER, CONG. RESEARCH SERV., RS22293, FEDERAL AND STATE LAWS
REGARDING PHARMACISTS WHO REFUSE TO DISPENSE CONTRACEPTIVES 3–4 (2005), available at http://maloney.house.gov/documents/olddocs/women/ALPHA/RS22293.pdf (citing In re Disciplinary Proceedings Against Neil T. Noesen, Final Decision and Order LS0310091PHM of the State of Wis. Before the Pharmacy Examining Bd. (April 13, 2005), available at https:// online.drl.wi.gov/decisions/2005/ls0310091phm-00068882.pdf); Am. Pub. Health Ass'n, supra note 24. 95.
N.Y. EDUC. LAW § 6530(30) (2010).
D.C. CODE § 3-1205.14 (2001). Many other states have similar patient abandonment
clauses. E.g. GA. CODE ANN. § 43-34-8 (2011); N.H. REV. STAT. ANN. § 329:17 (2011).
Fall 2010] TOWARDS PATIENT-CENTERED CARE 167
National professional associations for pharmacists, doctors, and
other medical and health professionals issue guidance to their mem-
bership outlining the duties owed to patients.97 These ethical duties re-
quire health professionals to privilege the welfare of the patient over
their own interests. They emphasize the informed consent paradigm,
which stresses that patients rather than physicians make decisions
about their care based on information physicians provide them ex-
plaining risks, benefits, and alternatives to a given treatment, is
central to modern medical ethics.98 These policies support the idea
that conscience protections for providers are acceptable only insofar
as arrangements are made to ensure that resulting refusals do not
interfere with patient care.99
1. American Medical Association
The American Medical Association (AMA), the nation's largest
provider group, recognizes the duty of physicians to place patient wel-
fare above all other considerations. "The relationship between patient
and physician is based on trust and gives rise to physicians' ethical
obligations to place patients' welfare above their own self-interest
and above obligations to other groups, and to advocate for their
patients' welfare."100 Provisions of the AMA's Code of Medical Ethics
make absolutely clear that physicians have a duty to provide patients
with all pertinent medical information and may not stop treating a
patient without providing assistance to patients to make alternate
97. See infra Part III.B. In addition, the American Academy of Physician Assistants has
also issued a guideline stating that "[p]hysician assistants have an ethical obligation to provide balanced and unbiased clinical information about reproductive health care." AM. ACAD. OF PHYSICIAN ASSISTANTS, GUIDELINES FOR ETHICAL CONDUCT FOR THE PHYSICIAN ASSISTANT PRO-FESSION 8 (2008), available at http://www.aapa.org/images/stories/Advocacy-Professional -Employment/19-EthicalConduct.doc.
98. Martha S. Swartz, "Conscience Clauses" or "Unconscionable Clauses": Personal Beliefs
Versus Professional Responsibilities, 6 YALE J. HEALTH POL'Y L. & ETHICS 269, 316 (2006).
99. See Letter from Am. Med. Ass'n et al., to Brenda Destro, Office of Public Health and
Science, Dep't of Health and Human Servs., at 2 (Sept. 24, 2008) ("[W]hile we support the legit-imate conscience rights of individual health care professionals, the exercise of these rights must be balanced against the fundamental obligations of the medical profession and physicians' paramount responsibility and commitment to serving the needs of their patients."). 100. AM. MED. ASS'N, CODE OF MED. ETHICS, § 10.015: 348 (2008–2009 ed. 2008).
AVE MARIA LAW REVIEW
arrangements for care.101 Furthermore, the AMA weighed in on the
issue of pharmacist refusals at its 2005 annual meeting. Noting the
potential impact on patient care, and the role of the pharmacist in
working with the physician to meet the needs of the patient, the AMA
stated that it would support laws that require dispensation or mean-
ingful and timely referral processes.102
2. American College of Obstetricians and Gynecologists
The American College of Obstetricians and Gynecologists (ACOG)
issued an advisory opinion in November 2007 describing the ethical
duties that reproductive health-care providers have to their patients,
despite any personal objections.103 It affirmed the primacy of respect
for patient autonomy in all medical professional conduct. The opinion
held that "[c]onscientious refusals that conflict with patient well-being
should be accommodated only if the primary duty to the patient can
be fulfilled."104
Specifically, ACOG's opinion makes clear that a physician's duty
is to provide "complete, scientifically accurate information about
options for reproductive health, including contraception, steriliza-
tion, and abortion" so that patients can make informed decisions.105
Charging doctors with the ethical obligation to provide scientific
information keeps physicians in an unambiguous role of providing
medical information rather than moral information and allows a pa-
tient to trust that she is getting relevant medical facts so that she can
make her own informed moral decisions.106 In addition to requiring
the provision of accurate information, the opinion requires doctors to
give advance notice of any objections that would cause them to deviate
101. Id. § 8.08: 245 –51 (discussing that informed consent must be honored by physicians; informed consent requires accurate presentation of medical facts and therapeutic alternatives);
id. § 8.082: 253 ("Withholding [pertinent] medical information from patients . . is ethically unacceptable."); id. § 10.01: 341– 47 (discussing that the physician may not terminate treatment without giving the patient reasonable assistance and time to make alternative arrangements for care). 102. Am.
Preserving Patients' Ability to Have Legally Valid Prescriptions Filled,
MEMORIAL RESOLUTIONS (2005). 103. The Limits of Conscientious Refusal in Reproductive Medicine, ACOG Committee Opinion No. 385 (Am. C. Obstetricians & Gynecologists, D.C.), Nov. 2007, http://www.acog.org/ from_home/publications/ethics/co385.pdf. 104. Id.
105. Id. at 3. 106. See id. at 3.
Fall 2010] TOWARDS PATIENT-CENTERED CARE 169
from standard practices to potential patients.107 The opinion states that
"[p]hysicians and other health care professionals have the duty to refer
patients in a timely manner to other providers if they do not feel that
they can in conscience provide the standard reproductive services
that their patients request."108 Emergency care must be provided de-
spite moral objection.109
This policy allows physicians to conform their behavior to their
ethical beliefs, but requires them to notify employers and potential
patients so that situations in which the patient would bear the burden
of the refusal will be minimized. And in emergencies, those instances
where advance notice and information does not allow the patient to
access care she needs from another provider, the physician has an ob-
ligation to treat her, preventing his personal beliefs from placing a ser-
ious burden on the patient. This system respects doctors' beliefs while
recognizing that professionalism requires that the patient come first.110
3. American Pharmacists Association
The American Pharmacists Association (APhA) recognizes the
right of conscience, but emphasizes that the duty falls on the phar-
macist to ensure patient access. "APhA recognizes the individual
pharmacist's right to exercise conscientious refusal and supports the
establishment of systems to ensure patient's access to legally pre-
scribed therapy without compromising the pharmacist's right of
conscientious refusal."111 Some pharmacists refuse to provide refer-
rals or transfer prescriptions, claiming that their desire to avoid be-
ing complicit in an act they find immoral should exempt them from
the standard obligation to provide the general standard of care.112
APhA has disagreed, stating that a pharmacist is prohibited from
108. Id. 109. Id. 110. The AMA's position regarding the primacy of the patient is echoed by public health organizations. See, e.g., Letter from Georges C. Benjamin to Michael O. Leavitt, supra note 12, at 1 ("APHA takes the position that patients' health and well-being must come first in health care delivery and in the formulation of health policy."). 111. AM. PHARMACISTS ASS'N, GOVERNMENT AFFAIRS ISSUE BRIEF: FEDERAL CONSCIENCE CLAUSE 3 (2009), available at http://www.pharmacist.com/AM/Template.cfm?Section=Home2& TEMPLATE=/CM/ContentDisplay.cfm&CONTENTID=15688. 112. See
Stein, supra note 10.
AVE MARIA LAW REVIEW
"taking any action to obstruct patient access to clinically appropriate,
legally prescribed therapy."113
APhA's policy, like those of the AMA and the ACOG, emphasizes
the primacy of the patient and strives to ensure that refusals do not
negatively impact that patient. The organization suggests that the ob-
jecting pharmacist is responsible for ensuring that a system is in place
so that the patient can get the medication, stating "[the] right of con-
science comes with responsibility to assure patient access to the le-
gally prescribed therapy."114 This policy has been interpreted by the
APhA to require a pharmacist to refer a prescription that he refuses to
fill on grounds of conscience to another pharmacist if referral is the
alternative system adopted by the pharmacist and his employer.115 The
APhA has extended the policy that employers and pharmacists
should establish systems that "provid[e] a timely alternative for con-
sumers" to the emergency contraception over-the-counter context.116
Moreover, APhA also urges pharmacists to carefully consider their
choice in practice setting to minimize conflicts, recognizing that they
might have to choose between their practice of the profession and
practice of their religion.117 The National Association of Boards of
Pharmacy wrote in its newsletter that "[p]harmacists should also con-
sider their career trajectory in light of their moral views; for example,
a pharmacist with strong beliefs against contraceptive drugs might pre-
fer to work in a setting that would not normally dispense EC."118
113. AM. PHARMACISTS ASS'N, supra note 111, at 3 ("APhA supports the ability of the phar-macist to step away, not in the way, and supports the establishment of an alternative system for delivery of patient care."). 114. Suzanne
Price, Conscience & Care: APhA Responds to Prevention Article, PHAR-
MACIST.COM (2004), http://www.pharmacist.com/AM/Template.cfm?Section=Search1& Template=/CM/HTMLDisplay.cfm&ContentID=8347 (quoting Susan Winckler, APhA's vice president of policy and communications). 115. See AM. PHARMACISTS ASS'N, supra note 111. 116. L. Michael Posey, Dual-Status Plan B Approved by FDA, PHARMACIST.COM (2006), http://www.pharmacist.com/AM/Template.cfm?Section=Pharmacy_News&Template=/CM/HTMLDisplay.cfm&ContentID=8007. 117. For example, a pharmacist who plans to refuse to provide particular drugs for moral reasons may prefer to work at a larger pharmacy with more than one pharmacist on duty at a time. See Letter from Georges C. Benjamin to Michael O. Leavitt, supra note 12, at 3 (describing how under Title VII small pharmacies with only one pharmacist available at a particular time "would have difficulty upholding the rights of a pharmacist who objects to filling certain pre-scriptions and the rights of patients to obtain those prescribed medications in a timely manner"). 118. Plan B Availability OTC Raises Logistical and Administrative Challenges, NAT'L ASS'N OF BOARDS OF PHARMACY NEWSL. (Nat'l Ass'n of Bds. of Pharmacy, Mount Prospect, Ill.), Nov.–Dec. 2006, at 199, 200, available at http://www.nabp.net/publications/assets/NovDec06NABP.pdf.
Fall 2010] TOWARDS PATIENT-CENTERED CARE 171
C. Fiduciary Duty
One legal theory that has yet to be sufficiently tested is whether
allowing nonmedical personal concerns to cloud professional judg-
ment or advice violates a physicians' fiduciary duty to the patient.
Courts have recognized that the physician is in a fiduciary relation-
ship with his patient.119 Breach of fiduciary duty "claims object to the
physician's failure to conform to the ethical principles that undivided
loyalty to a patient should guide a physician's decisions, and that any
influence on a physician's decisions—other than the patient's welfare—
must be disclosed to the patient."120 The fiduciary duty exists in the
physician-patient relationship because the professional is in a posi-
tion of power with respect to the vulnerable patient, who is depen-
dent on the physician for competent and responsible medical care.121
While the fiduciary duty sometimes
preclude[s] the fiduciary from engaging in economic or other arrange-
ments that may create a conflict of interest between the fiduciary and
the beneficiary of the relationship, . . in some instances the risks
posed by such arrangements may be mitigated by the fiduciary's
disclosure of and the beneficiary's consent to the arrangement.122
For example, failure to disclose a financial interest, which may affect
the doctor's advice, violates his fiduciary duty, but he may be allowed
to continue the conflicting economic activity so long as it is disclosed.
Similarly, failure to disclose a moral bias, which may affect the medical
care or information offered by a physician, could violate his fiduciary
duty, but full disclosure of the professional's limitations to the patient
might be sufficient to comply with the fiduciary duty so long as the
disclosure mitigates the potential for harm flowing from the refusal.
119. Mary Anne Bobinski, Autonomy and Privacy: Protecting Patients from Their Physicians, 55 U. PITT. L. REV. 291, 350 n.211 (1994) (citing Gonzalez v. Palo Verde Mental Health Servs., 783 P.2d 833, 835 (Ariz. Ct. App. 1989)); Mary Crossley, Infected Judgment: Legal Responses to Phy-
sician Bias, 48 VILL. L. REV. 195, 251 (2003) (citing Hoopes v. Hammargren, 725 P.2d 238, 242 (Nev. 1986)). 120. Crossley,
supra note 119, at 249.
121. Maxine M. Harrington, The Ever-Expanding Health Care Conscience Clause: The Quest
for Immunity in the Struggle Between Professional Duties and Moral Beliefs, 34 FLA. ST. U. L. REV. 779, 809–10 (2007). 122. Crossley,
supra note 119, at 252.
AVE MARIA LAW REVIEW
D. Recognition in Malpractice and Tort Law
"Health professionals owe duties to their patients according to
accepted standards of care and, in the absence of a conscience clause,
cannot simply refuse to treat or counsel their patients without ex-
posure to liability for abandonment [or] malpractice."123 Medical pro-
fessionals "have a duty of care to conform to the generally recognized
and accepted practices in their profession."124 If a doctor fails to pro-
vide a treatment in specific circumstances where the standard of care
calls for it, he could be held civilly liable for malpractice.125
Most states treat failure to provide informed consent as a medical
malpractice claim where the specific failure to provide sufficient infor-
mation is measured against the information required by the standard
of care.126 However, in many states it is difficult to win a malpractice
suit based on lack of informed consent because one must articulate a
tangible injury. One such injury resulting from lack of informed con-
sent is "wrongful birth," a tort recognized in many states when a
physician negligently fails to either diagnose a genetic defect or fails
to inform the parents of the need for or the results of genetic testing.
"Damages are awarded for emotional distress, medical expenses
associated with pregnancy and birth, and, in some states, expenses
the parents will incur from raising an impaired child."127 There is also
a possibility for recovery for a category of nonphysical damages, some-
times known as dignitary harms; the claim is that the absence of
informed consent is an injury "to [the] plaintiff's personal dignity and
right of privacy."128
123. Harrington,
supra note 121, at 804.
supra note 16, at 157 (quoting Evans v. Rite Aid Corp., 478 S.E.2d 846, 849 (S.C.
1996)). 125. See
NAT'L WOMEN'S LAW CTR., supra note 19, at 1.
supra note 119, at 248.
127. Harrington,
supra note 121, at 812 (citing Wendy F. Hensel, The Disabling Impact of
Wrongful Birth and Wrongful Life Actions, 40 HARV. C.R.-C.L. L. REV. 141, 142– 43, 160 (2005) (stating that more than half of all jurisdictions have endorsed "wrongful birth" actions)). Many states, however, have refused to recognize a "wrongful life" action brought on behalf of the impaired child under a variety of concerns over an inability to value any life. Hensel, supra, at 161; see also Willis v. Wu, 607 S.E.2d 63, 65 – 66 (S.C. 2004) (discussing the difference between wrongful birth, wrongful life, and wrongful pregnancy actions). 128. Lugenbuhl v. Dowling, 701 So. 2d 447, 455 – 56 (La. 1997); see also Alan Meisel, A
"Dignitary Tort" as a Bridge Between the Idea of Informed Consent and the Law of Informed
Consent, 16 J.L. MED. & HEALTH CARE 210, 212 (1988) (noting that courts have increasingly allowed tort claims to protect dignitary interests).
Fall 2010] TOWARDS PATIENT-CENTERED CARE 173
An individual who is refused her prescription may have a private
cause of action against a pharmacy or pharmacist. "Case law supports
the proposition that the pharmacist, as the possessor of a legal mono-
poly on the dispensing of prescription drugs, may not exercise non-
medical discretion by refusing to dispense prescriptions he or she
finds objectionable, but rather must accurately fill all safe, valid pre-
scriptions presented by a client."129 Disclosure of private medical
information in a public place, which often accompanies pharmacy
refusals, is also actionable under various state and federal laws.130
E. Duty of the Institution
In general, hospitals do not have to provide any particular care or
allow any particular procedure. However, there are slight limitations
on institutional ability to refuse treatment in hospitals receiving
public funds, such as Medicare funding. These hospitals have add-
itional obligations regarding informed consent and emergency care
which could be breached by refusals. The Medicare Conditions of Parti-
cipation regulation regarding informed consent states:
The patient or his or her representative (as allowed under State law)
has the right to make informed decisions regarding his or her care.
The patient's rights include being informed of his or her health status,
being involved in care planning and treatment, and being able to
request or refuse treatment.131
Furthermore, the Emergency Medical Treatment and Active Labor
Act (EMTALA) imposes a duty on hospitals to stabilize a patient who
is in unstable condition and prohibits transfer of an unstable patient.132
EMTALA does not provide any exemption for the moral, religious or
ethical beliefs of providers or institutions.
supra note 16, at 157 (citing Coyle v. Richardson-Merrell, Inc., 584 A.2d 1383, 1386
(Pa. 1991); Heredia v. Johnson, 827 F. Supp. 1522, 1525 (D. Nev. 1993)). 130. The Health Insurance Portability and Accountability Act of 1996 (HIPAA) requires providers, including pharmacies, to protect patient information. See generally Pub. L. No. 104-191, 110 Stat. 1936. The privacy provision is enforced by the Department of Health and Human Services Office for Civil Rights. OFFICE FOR CIVIL RIGHTS, U.S. DEP'T OF HEALTH & HUMAN SERVS., SUMMARY OF THE HIPAA PRIVACY RULE 1 (2003), available at http://www.hhs.gov/ ocr/privacy/hipaa/understanding/summary/privacysummary.pdf. 131. 42 C.F.R. § 482.13(b)(2) (2009). 132. 42 U.S.C. § 1395dd(b)(1), (c)(1) (2000).
AVE MARIA LAW REVIEW
Pharmacies in some states have state law obligations to stock or
dispense medications. For example, some chain and individual phar-
macies refuse to stock emergency contraception. In some states, such
stocking bans could violate provisions in state pharmacy laws that
require pharmacies to meet "community needs" or maintain an ade-
quate stock of drugs.133 The "community needs" argument was suc-
cessful in challenging Wal-Mart's well-publicized corporation-wide
ban on stocking emergency contraception.134 In Massachusetts, local
advocates filed a lawsuit and complaints with the pharmacy board on
behalf of three women who were denied emergency contraception at
Wal-Mart, alleging a violation of Massachusetts's community needs
provision.135 The Massachusetts Board of Pharmacy responded unani-
mously, finding that the Wal-Mart policy violated this provision and
that Wal-Mart pharmacies in the state are required to stock and
III. INADEQUATE PROTECTION OF PATIENTS
General informed consent and standard of care doctrines require
medical professionals to provide the patient with medical information
from which she can make an informed decision regarding care. Re-
fusal clauses "are statutory provisions that allow people or entities to
opt out of complying with laws and regulations based on religious
or moral objections."137 Despite the robust basis in generally appli-
cable law and medical ethics for placing protection of the patient at
the center of medical decision-making, current conscience laws allow
the religious beliefs of individual and institutional providers to take
precedence over the needs of patients. Laws which allow medical
professionals to opt out of providing the generalized standard of care
and informed consent allow providers to abdicate their role as neutral
e.g., IND. CODE § 25-26-13-18(a)(2) (2010) ("The pharmacy will maintain a sufficient
stock of emergency and frequently prescribed drugs and devices as to adequately serve and protect the public health."); S.D. CODIFIED LAWS § 36-11-41(1) (2010) ("The pharmacy . . shall possess a stock of pharmaceuticals adequate to serve the needs of the community in which the pharmacy is located."). 134. Michael
In Reversal, Wal-Mart Will Sell Contraceptive, N.Y. TIMES, Mar. 4,
2006, at C4; see also Dana Canedy, Wal-Mart Decides Against Selling a Contraceptive, N.Y. TIMES, May 14, 1999, at C1 (discussing Wal-Mart's initial decision not to carry Plan B). 135. See Complaint at 1–3, McCarty v. Wal-Mart Stores, Inc., No. 06-0422 (Mass. Dist. Ct. filed Feb. 1, 2006). 136. Bruce
State Orders Wal-Mart to Sell Morning-After Pill, BOSTON GLOBE, Feb. 15,
2006, at F1. 137. Fogel & Rivera, supra note 17, at 1.
Fall 2010] TOWARDS PATIENT-CENTERED CARE 175
provider of medical rather than moral information and to co-opt the
role of the patient as decision maker by substituting the professional's
moral judgments for the patient's.
A. Legal Protections for the Right to Refuse and Impact on
Patients' Rights
Professional ethical obligations are undermined by laws that exempt
practitioners from the consequences that generally flow from failure
to follow the applicable professional standards. Unfortunately, pro-
fessional ethical obligations without legal enforcement are not always
sufficient to protect patients. A poll reported in the New England
Journal of Medicine showed that 18 percent of the doctors surveyed
think that they are not obligated to provide a referral, and 8 percent
think it is fine to withhold information about treatment options.138
These attitudes show the willingness of some providers to privilege
their personal beliefs over patient welfare and autonomy despite pro-
fessional ethical obligations. Too many laws that govern refusals do
not attempt to minimize the effect of the providers' beliefs on the
patient. Current laws, which allow providers to make conscience--
based refusals to provide care without fear of legal consequences, fail
to protect the patient from harm as a result of these refusals.
The first refusal clause was the Church Amendment, passed after
Roe v. Wade to allow individuals and entities that receive federal
funding to resist requirements that they perform or provide facilities
for abortions or sterilizations if those procedures would be "contrary to
[the individual or entity's] religious beliefs or moral convictions."139
After the Church Amendment, states then passed their own laws,
usually expanding the types of services, health-care professionals, and
institutions that were allowed to refuse health-care services. Forty-
seven states and the District of Columbia have at least one law which
allows medical providers or institutions to refuse at least one medical
service.140 Out of these states, only three and the District of Columbia
138. Curlin et al., supra note 6, at 597. 139. 42 U.S.C. § 300a–7(b) (1976); JODY FEDER, CONG. RESEARCH SERV., RS21428, THE HISTORY AND EFFECT OF ABORTION CONSCIENCE CLAUSE LAWS 1–3 (2006) (discussing the history of conscience clause laws in response to Roe v. Wade, 410 U.S. 113 (1973)). 140. ALASKA STAT. § 18.16.010 (2010); ARIZ. REV. STAT. § 36-2154 (LexisNexis 2010); ARK. CODE ANN. §§ 20-16-304, -601 (2010); CAL. HEALTH & SAFETY CODE § 123420 (West 2010); CAL. PROBATE CODE §§ 4734 – 4736 (West 2010); COLO. REV. STAT. §§ 18-6-104, 25-6-102, -207, 27-10.5-132 (2010); CONN. AGENCIES REGS. §19-13-D54(f) (2010); DEL. CODE ANN. tit. 24, § 1791 (2010); D.C. CODE § 22-B9006 (LexisNexis 2010); FLA. STAT. ANN. §§ 381.0051(6), 390.0111(8) (West 2009);
AVE MARIA LAW REVIEW
have exceptions to each refusal law that requires a provider or insti-
tution to take actions that may contravene his or its objections where
patient safety or an emergency requires it.141 Iowa includes a pro-
vision in its law governing refusals that requires the professional or
institution to provide emergency care that may be in conflict with his
or its conscience when the patient's life is endangered, and three other
states include a life exception in at least one, but not all, of their laws
allowing refusal.142 This leaves forty-three states with at least one
refusal law that does not ensure that patients will receive emergency
care if that care conflicts with a provider's conscience, even in some GA. CODE ANN. §§ 16-12-142, 31-20-6, 49-7-6 (2010); GA. COMP. R. & REGS. 480-5-.03(n) (2010); HAW. REV. STAT. ANN. §§ 327E-7, 453-16 (LexisNexis 2010); IDAHO CODE ANN. §§ 18-611 to -612, 39-3915 (LexisNexis Supp. 2010); 745 ILL. COMP. STAT. ANN. 70/1–14 (West 2010); IND. CODE ANN. §§ 16-34-1-3 to -7 (LexisNexis 2010); IOWA CODE §§ 146.1 to .2 (2010); KAN. STAT. ANN. §§ 65-443 to -444, -446 to -447 (2009); KY. REV. STAT. ANN. § 311.800 (LexisNexis 2010); LA. REV. STAT. ANN. § 40:1299.31 to .33 (2009); ME. REV. STAT. tit. 22, §§ 1591–1592, 1903; tit. 34-B, § 7016 (2009); MD. CODE ANN., HEALTH-GEN. § 20-214(a) (LexisNexis 2010); MASS. ANN. LAWS ch. 112, § 12I; ch. 272, § 21B (LexisNexis 2010); MICH. COMP. LAWS SERV. §§ 333.20181 to .20184 (LexisNexis 2010); MINN. STAT. §§ 145.42, .414, .925(6) (2009); MISS. CODE ANN. §§ 41-41-215(5), 41-107-5, -7, -11 (West 2007); MO. REV. STAT. §§ 188.100, .105, .110, .115, .120, 197.032 (2009); MONT. CODE ANN. §§ 50-5-501 to -505, -20-111 (2010); NEB. REV. STAT. ANN. §§ 28-337 to -341 (LexisNexis 2010); NEV. REV. STAT. ANN. §§ 449.191, 632.475 (West 2010); N.J. STAT. ANN. § 2A:65A-1 to -4, 30:11-9 (West 2010); N.M. STAT. ANN. §§ 24-7A-7(E), -8-6, 30-5-2 (LexisNexis 2010); N.Y. CIV. RIGHTS LAW § 79-i (McKinney 2009); N.Y. COMP. CODES R. & REGS. tit. 10, § 405.9(b)(10); tit. 18, § 463.6(d) (2010); N.C. GEN. STAT. § 14-45.1(e) (2010); N.D. CENT. CODE ANN. § 23-16-14 (West 2010); OHIO REV. CODE ANN. § 4731.91 (West 2010); OKLA. STAT. ANN. tit. 63, §§ 1-728a–f, -741 (West 2010); OR. REV. STAT. ANN. §§ 435.225, .475, .485 (West 2010); 43 PA. CONS. STAT. ANN. § 955.2 (West 2010); 16 PA. CODE §§ 51.1 to .2, .31–.33, .41–.44, .51–.52, .61 (2010); R.I. GEN. LAWS ANN. § 23-17-11 (West 2010); S.C. CODE ANN. §§ 44-41-40, -50 (2010); S.D. CODIFIED LAWS §§ 34-23A-11 to -14, 36-11-70 (2010); TENN. CODE ANN. §§ 39-15-204 to -205, 68-34-104 (2010); TEX. OCC. CODE ANN. §§ 103.001 to .004 (West 2010); UTAH CODE ANN. § 76-7-306 (West 2010); VA. CODE ANN. §§ 18.2-75, 32.1-134 (2010); WASH. REV. CODE §§ 9.02.150, 48.43.065 (2010); W.VA. CODE §§ 16-2B-4, -11-1, -30-12 (2010); WIS. STAT. §§ 253.07(3)(b), .09, 441.06(6), 448.03(5)(a) (2008); WYO. STAT. ANN. §§ 35-6-105 to -106, -114, 42-5-101 to -102 (2010); the states without medical refusal laws are Alabama, New Hamp-shire, and Vermont. 141. CAL. HEALTH & SAFETY CODE § 123420(d) (West 2010); D.C. CODE § 22-B9006 (LexisNexis 2010); MD. CODE ANN., HEALTH-GEN § 20-214(d) (2010); and Nevada, NEV. REV. STAT. ANN. § 449.191 (West 2010). Maryland's emergency exception is very limited in that it exempts from immunity from liability only in cases where the refusal resulted in death or serious long-lasting injury and was otherwise contrary to the standards of care; therefore, a doctor would not incur liability for refusal in an emergency situation where the patient lived and incurred only temporary serious injury. Illinois and Louisiana have an emergency exception in some, but not all, of their refusal laws. See 745 ILL. COMP. STAT. ANN. 70/6 (West 2010) & 70/9 (2010); LA. REV. STAT. ANN. § 40:1299.34 (2009); but see LA. REV. STAT. ANN. § 40:1299.31 (2009) (shielding from liability and discrimination health-care practitioners who refuse "for any reason to recommend, counsel, perform, assist with or accommodate an abortion"). 142. See,
e.g., IOWA CODE § 146.1 (2010); see also IDAHO CODE ANN. § 18-611(6) (LexisNexis
Supp. 2004); MO. REV. STAT. § 188.100(2) (2009); OKLA. STAT. ANN. tit. 63, § 1-728c(1), -741(C) (West 2010); TEX. OCC. CODE ANN. § 103.004 (West 2010).
Fall 2010] TOWARDS PATIENT-CENTERED CARE 177
situations where the patient's life is in danger.143 While the
professional organizations provide ethical guidance suggesting that
providers should place considerations of the patient's health above all
other considerations, these ethical guidelines do not sufficiently
protect patients because many providers privilege their personal
beliefs over the patient's health by allowing their nonmedical beliefs
to justify going beyond refusing to provide care when it can be
provided by a different practitioner into the professionally unsound
realm of refusing to provide care when that refusal will have adverse
effects on the patient's health outcome or refusing to provide enough
information for a patient to make a meaningful decision.
In addition to permitting refusals, twenty-seven states shift
responsibility for injury resulting from refusals to the patient by
immunizing individuals or hospitals from liability stemming from a
refusal to provide care.144 For example, an Oklahoma law passed in
April 2010 prohibits damages in wrongful birth lawsuits where the
medical professionals withhold information about abnormal fetal
development from a pregnant woman to ensure that she will not
choose to terminate the pregnancy.145 This means that medical pro-
fessionals will not be subject to liability if they diagnose abnormal
fetal development, but withhold this information from the parents,
determining on the woman's behalf that she will continue the preg-
nancy and birth the child unprepared for the emotional, financial,
and physical toll and deprived of the opportunity to come to terms
with her own moral worldview and determine what is best for her
and her family. The law absolves doctors of the consequences of their
refusal to abide by modern medical norms of informed consent, which
requires that doctors share medical information and diagnoses in
143. See supra notes 140–142 (Alabama, New Hampshire, and Vermont do not have refusal laws, and California, Iowa, Maryland, and Nevada include exceptions to every refusal law). 144. ALASKA STAT. § 18.16.010(b) (2010); ARK. CODE ANN. § 20-16-601(a) (2010); DEL. CODE ANN. tit. 24, § 1791(a) (2010); FLA. STAT. ANN. § 390.0111(8) (2009); GA. CODE ANN. § 16-12-142 (2009); HAW. REV. STAT. ANN. § 453-16(e) (LexisNexis 2010); 745 ILL. COMP. STAT. ANN. 70/4 (West 2010); KAN. STAT. ANN. § 65-443 (2009); KY. REV. STAT. ANN. § 311.800 (LexisNexis 2010); LA. REV. STAT. ANN. § 40:1299.31 (2009); MD. CODE ANN., HEALTH-GEN. § 20-214(a)(2) (2010); MICH. COMP. LAWS SERV. § 333.20181 (LexisNexis 2010); MINN. STAT. § 145.42(1) (2009); MISS. CODE ANN. § 41-107-5(2) (West 2007); MO. REV. STAT. § 197.032(1) (2009); MONT. CODE ANN. § 50-20-111 (2010); N.J. STAT. § 2A:65A-3 (2010); N.Y. CIV. RIGHTS LAW § 79-i(2) (2009); OHIO REV. CODE ANN. § 4731.91(C) (West 2010); OKLA. STAT. ANN. tit. 63, § 1-741 (West 2010); OR. REV. STAT. ANN. § 435.475(1) (West 2010) (hospital only); 43 PA. CONS. STAT. ANN. § 955.2(a) (West 2010); S.C. CODE ANN. § 44-41-40 (2010); S.D. CODIFIED LAWS § 34-23A-12 (2010); UTAH CODE ANN. § 76-7-306(1) (West 2010); WIS. STAT. § 253.09 (2008); WYO. STAT. ANN. § 35-6-106 (2010). 145. OKLA. STAT. tit. 63, § 1-741.11(C) (West 2010).
AVE MARIA LAW REVIEW
order to allow the patient to draw their own moral conclusions and
make medical decisions for themselves. In many cases, by allowing
refusal to provide information and referrals without liability, the laws
governing refusal work to increase the harms that refusal to provide
services causes to the patient by ensuring that a refusal by an indi-
vidual provider will result in the patient not being able to access the
standard of medical care.
Many state laws have expanded the scope of federal refusal law
by expanding the services that may be refused. Fourteen states have
extended refusal clauses to services related to contraception for at
least some practitioners.146 For example, Idaho passed a refusal law in
2010 that exempts health-care professionals licensed by the state who
refuse to provide a number of services, including "dispensation of an
abortifacient drug," from liability.147 The law defines abortifacient to
include "emergency contraception."148 This extends the ability to le-
gally refuse to provide services beyond abortion because emergency
contraception, like regular contraception, functions primarily by pre-
venting ovulation and may prevent fertilization of a released ovum or
implantation. This bill includes a form of contraception, which is not
chemically different from other forms of contraception, among the
services a provider may refuse without consequence, extending the
realm of refusal beyond objection to abortion and into objection to
contraception.149 In addition, because the abortion pill, also known as
RU-486 or mifepristone, which actually does terminate an existing
pregnancy, is not available at pharmacies, the Idaho law extends the
ability to refuse to provide the general standard of care to pharmacists
where a refusal law dealing only with abortion and not with contra-
ception would not.
Other state laws expand exemption from the legal consequences
of not complying with otherwise applicable professional norms to a
wider range of practitioners. For example, many state laws allow phar-
macists to refuse to fill prescriptions based on their religious, moral,
146. GUTTMACHER INST., STATE POLICIES IN BRIEF: REFUSING TO PROVIDE HEALTH SERVICES 1 (2011), available at http://www.guttmacher.org/statecenter/spibs/spib_RPHS.pdf. 147. IDAHO CODE ANN. § 18-611 (LexisNexis 2010). 148. Id.; but see supra note 2 (stating that it is scientifically clear that levenorgestal, the traditional form of emergency contraception, does not cause abortions, defined as the termination of an existing pregnancy). 149. This law would also expand the ability to refuse without consequence to cases where doctors and pharmacists refuse to dispense the Ella, which is not an identical chemical to other forms of birth control, but is nonetheless classified as a contraceptive by the FDA. For additional discussion see supra note 2.
Fall 2010] TOWARDS PATIENT-CENTERED CARE 179
or personal beliefs or protect pharmacists from adverse employment
action for doing so.150 In 2008, the George W. Bush Administration's
Department of Health and Human Services (HHS) issued a Rule on
Provider Conscience, which interpreted existing law to expand the
universe of health-care services that can be refused and individuals
who may refuse.151 The Obama Administration has taken inconclu-
sive steps towards rescinding this regulation out of concern about
patient access to contraception and other services.152
While the patient's ability to make her own medical decisions is
limited by laws which exempt providers from the duty to provide
information, laws theoretically designed to protect patients who are
making abortion decisions exacerbate the problem. While some states
statutorily protect a woman's right not to be coerced into having
an abortion,153 these laws do not provide equivalent protection of the
woman's right not to be coerced against having an abortion.154 Some
state laws even encourage or require doctors to give inconclusive
medical information to patients considering abortion.155
Laws designed to protect practitioners from conflicts with in-
stitutions are similarly one-sided. Refusal policies, as outlined infra,
allow providers in non-objecting hospitals to refuse to provide certain
services without professional consequence, but they do not protect
150. See ARK. CODE ANN. § 20-16-601 (2010); GA. COMP. R. & REGS. 480-5-.03 (2010); MISS. CODE ANN. § 41-107-5 (West 2007); S.D. CODIFIED LAWS § 36-11-70 (2010). 151. 73 Fed. Reg. 78,072 (Dec. 19, 2008) (to be codified at 45 C.F.R. pt. 88); see also Letter from Rick Pollack, Exec. Vice Pres., Am. Hosp. Ass'n, to Michael O. Leavitt, Sec'y, U.S. Dep't of Health & Human Servs. 1 (Sept. 25, 2008), available at http://www.regulations.gov/search/ Regs/home.html#documentDetail?R=090000648071ebc8 (asking for more than the typical 30-day comment period for considering the adoption of administrative rules). 152. See
Rob Stein, Heath Workers' "Conscience" Rule Set to Be Voided, WASH. POST, Feb.
28, 2009, at A1. 153. See Monthly State Update: Major Developments in 2010, Prohibiting Forcing a Woman
to Have an Abortion, GUTTMACHER.ORG (Oct. 1, 2010), http://www.guttmacher.org/statecenter/ updates/index.html#coercion (stating that eleven states have introduced requirements that a woman seeking an abortion be informed that she cannot be coerced into having an abortion, mentioning specifically legislation passed in 2010 in Oklahoma and Tennessee); Counseling and
Waiting Periods for Abortion, STATE POLICIES IN BRIEF 1–2 (Guttmacher Inst., New York, N.Y.), Oct. 1, 2010, at 1, 2 [hereinafter STATE POLICIES IN BRIEF], http://guttmacher.com/statecenter/spibs/ spib_MWPA.pdf (illustrating in a chart that nine states (Alabama, Arizona, Arkansas, Kansas, Louisiana, Pennsylvania, Utah, West Virginia, and Wisconsin) have an anti-coercion policy). 154. See ALA. CODE § 26-23A-5 (LexisNexis 2009); KAN. STAT. ANN. § 65-6710 (2009); LA. REV. STAT. ANN. § 40:1299.35.6 (2009); UTAH CODE ANN. § 76-7-305.5, -312 (LexisNexis 2010). 155. See
STATE POLICIES IN BRIEF, supra note 153, at 3 (illustrating in a chart that two states
(South Dakota and Texas) inaccurately portray risk to future fertility in their abortion counseling materials, and five states (Alaska, Mississippi, Oklahoma, Texas, and West Virginia) assert a possible link between breast cancer and abortion).
AVE MARIA LAW REVIEW
physicians who want to provide the service in an institution that re-
fuses.156 This leaves a physician who does not object to a particular
service and believes he has a professional obligation to provide that
service without protection from an institutional policy prohibiting
such a service.157
B. Limitations of Title VII
Title VII requires employers to accommodate employees' religious
beliefs, but allows employers to refuse accommodations that would
constitute an "undue hardship" on the employer's business.158 Courts
have found that employers do not have to accommodate employees'
religious practices if they burden patients, customers or coworkers
because such burdens present an "undue hardship" under Title VII.159
In order for this standard to protect the patient, the employee must be
willing to disclose the need for a religious accommodation in time to
set up an accommodation that meets the needs of all patients, and the
employer must want to protect the patient's access to health-care serv-
ices and information through an appropriate accommodation and
alternate delivery system. Title VII provides a standard for employers
who want to set up a system to protect the patient while accommo-
dating providers' religious beliefs, but it fails to protect patients where
the employer is a participant or uninterested bystander in the refusal.
156. See, e.g., Watkins v. Mercy Med. Ctr., 364 F. Supp. 799, 803 (D. Idaho 1973) (discussing the prevailing right of religious hospitals to refuse to grant staff privileges to a doctor who refuses to abide by religious restrictions on sterilization or abortion procedure within the institution), aff'd, 520 F.2d 894 (9th Cir. 1975). 157. Stulberg
supra note 77, at 729.
158. Letter from Am. Med. Ass'n to Brenda Destro, supra note 99, at 3. 159. See, e.g., Anderson v. U.S.F. Logistics, Inc., 274 F.3d 470, 475 –76 (7th Cir. 2001) (holding that employer's ban against employee using the phrase "Have a Blessed Day" with a certain customer, but not all, was a reasonable accommodation); Chalmers v. Tulon Co. of Richmond, 101 F.3d 1012, 1021 (4th Cir. 1996) (noting, in dicta, the need for a company to protect itself from other employees' claims of religious harassment when one employee claimed that religious belief compelled her to write letters to coworkers questioning their behavior); Grant v. Fairview Hosp. & Healthcare Servs., No. 02-4232, 2004 WL 326694, at *5 (D. Minn. Feb. 18, 2004) (holding that employer was not required to risk breaching duty of care to patients to accom-modate ultrasound technician whose religious beliefs compelled him to counsel patients against having abortions).
Fall 2010] TOWARDS PATIENT-CENTERED CARE 181
IV. CONCLUSION: TOWARD PATIENT-CENTERED CARE
Individual health-care providers are entitled to their religious and
moral beliefs and are also entitled to accommodations for these beliefs
so long as such accommodations do not impose providers' beliefs on
a patient by limiting her access to care.160 Patients are entitled to a
standard of care based on scientific medical understanding that is
unaffected by a medical professionals' personal beliefs. Medical ethics
require health-care providers to put the patient first. Therefore, poli-
cies must be crafted to provide the maximum protection for providers'
conscientious objections consistent with the obligation to ensure that
patients receive care that is based on consideration of the patient's
medical condition and the patient's personal beliefs.161
A. Amendments to Existing Conscience Clauses
Existing conscience clauses are too vague and leave patients vul-
nerable to denials of information, referrals and care. They focus on
provider rights to the exclusion of patient rights by setting up systems
of refusal without accompanying requirements that providers ensure
that their refusal to participate in particular services will not com-
promise the patient's ability to access those services. Refusal clauses
are especially egregious when they privilege institutional "conscience"
over individual patients' rights because there is an extreme imbalance
of power between institutional actors and individual patients. Laws
governing refusals should not make exceptions to the few patient pro-
tective duties that institutions do have under generally applicable law,
such as the duty to provide emergency care in certain circumstances
or the duty not to abandon patients, because such exceptions simply
shift legal responsibility for the harms that result from refusals from
the institution to the patient.
But policies that accommodate individual refusals to participate in
services can ensure the type of "seamless" patient interaction support-
ed by the major medical associations. Requirements that an individual
notify the employer ahead of time allow institutions to prepare for in-
160. See Fogel & Rivera, supra note 17, at 8. 161. See Fogel & Rivera, supra note 76, at 728–29 ("[L]aws and regulations . . [should] protect individual rights of both patients and individual health care professionals . . In the reproductive health context, it is possible to accommodate individual—as opposed to insti-tutional—refusals to provide certain health services without imposing inappropriate burdens on patients' rights.").
AVE MARIA LAW REVIEW
dividual refusals so that the employer can determine whether it can
accommodate the employee's refusal and put a system in place to
guarantee seamless delivery of care to the individual. For example,
laws governing refusals in the pharmacy can ensure timely delivery
by requiring that the pharmacy provide in-stock medications while
encouraging individual objecting pharmacists to notify the employer
in advance so that their personal preferences can be accommodated
where possible. Such a law might require that where a medication is
in stock it must be provided at that particular pharmacy in a timely
manner (for example, by having a non-objecting employee provide
it), that where it is not in stock a patient will be given options for
obtaining the medication, including having the pharmacy order the
medication or transferring the prescription to a pharmacy that is known
to have the medication in stock, and that harassment of patients or mis-
representation of drug activity or availability by any pharmacy em-
ployee will remain prohibited.162
Conscience laws should also be amended to make it clear that
employers retain their right, pursuant to Title VII, to deny accommo-
dation that may cause harm to patients.163 Laws governing refusals
should not shield providers or institutions from liability for harms
resulting from their refusals, thus providing employers an incentive
to ensure that the generally applicable standard of care is always met.
The burden should remain on health-care professionals and institu-
tions to ensure that the patient receives treatment that meets the stan-
All laws allowing individual medical professionals to refuse to
participate in services should include clear emergency exceptions when
refusals are not permitted. Conscience clauses should be amended to
make clear that they do not abridge individual medical professionals'
duty to provide the information necessary for informed consent. Laws
which allow refusals to participate should ensure that they are consis-
tent with doctors' ethical duty not to deprive a patient of her right to
make decisions about her own medical care by withholding infor-
mation. State policymakers should clarify that laws governing refusals
Am. Pub. Health Ass'n, supra note 24 (recommending three principles for refusal
policies to follow). Advocates for patient-centered pharmacy refusal laws can contact the Na-tional Women's Law Center for model dispensation law language drafted to incorporate the highest standards for the practice of pharmacy and ensures seamless delivery of all legally prescribed medications. 163. See
Adam Sonfield, Delineating the Obligations that Come with Conscientious Refusal:
A Question of Balance, GUTTMACHER POL'Y REV., Summer 2009, at 6, 7.
Fall 2010] TOWARDS PATIENT-CENTERED CARE 183
do not give health-care providers the right to attempt to manipulate
women in their decision-making by presenting information that is not
medically accurate or is misleading, or by presenting information in a
psychologically abusive manner.
B. Enforcement of Current Protections
Health-care providers, employers and employees alike, need con-
sistent enforcement of both Title VII protections and informed consent
requirements so that they can align their expectations and behavior.
Employers must know the requirements of informed consent and emer-
gency treatment so that they can set outer limits on possible religious
accommodations. Employees must have confidence that there is a
system in place that will accommodate their religious beliefs when
possible without burdening patient care so that they are comfortable
sharing these beliefs with employers before a refusal situation arises,
allowing the employer to create an accommodation that will not bur-
den patients.164
1. Informed Consent and Other Legally Enforceable Duties
Patients and advocates must file more complaints to state and fed-
eral enforcement agencies, professional boards and licensing agencies
to ensure that professional and legal obligations, such as obligations
to ensure informed consent or to provide emergency treatment, will
be fulfilled.165 These complaints, based on existing laws and regula-
tions, such as those prohibiting patient abandonment or defining
unprofessional conduct, ensure that medical providers are aware of
their professional responsibilities. They also highlight the outer bounds
of conscience protection laws by demarcating acceptable ways to con-
duct a refusal that do not impact patient care from the unprofessional
refusals which impose providers' beliefs on patients.
164. See id. at 6–9 (illustrating that in order for health-care professionals or institutions to exercise their conscience without "intentionally or otherwise block[ing] patients' access to care . . any objection to providing a specific service must be made transparent to all relevant parties"). 165. For an example of a complaint, see Letter from Laura W. Murphy, Director, Washington Legislative Office, Am. Civil Liberties Union et al., to Marilyn Tavenner, Acting Administrator, Ctrs. for Medicare and Medicaid Servs. (July 1, 2010), available at http://www.aclu.org/files/assets/ Letter_to_CMS_Final_PDF.pdf.
AVE MARIA LAW REVIEW
Clear enforcement of Title VII would allow institutions and in-
dividual employees to ensure that accommodations of employees
would not interfere with the seamless provision of services to
patients. When employers are aware of Title VII requirements, they
can talk to employees about whether or not they need accommoda-
tions, and can set up systems that accommodate employee refusals
without compromising patient care by having another employee
take their place.166 Employees who simply want to be able to avoid
providing services to which they object benefit when they are able to
disclose their need for accommodation before a religious refusal situa-
tion arises, allowing their employer the opportunity to accommodate
them in a way that will not present an undue burden. The patient also
benefits because a clear system to accommodate employees' known
religious needs allows the employer to ensure that the patient will not
be harmed by the accommodation.167
C. Patient Education
Most people do not know that doctors can be restricted from pro-
viding certain services based on their affiliations with religious insti-
tutions. Similarly, patients may be unaware of their providers'
individual objections and refusals to disclose all treatment options or
to make referrals, or may be unaware that their insurance plan is
religiously affiliated and will not cover certain services. Patients who
are unaware that providers may be withholding medical inform-
ation, advice, and care based on the providers' personal beliefs or the
institutions' nonmedical-based restrictions are unable to protect them-
selves by asking about refusals and recognizing situations in which
they may have experienced a refusal.
166. Id. at 7 (discussing EQUAL EMP'T OPPORTUNITY COMM'N, COMPLIANCE MANUAL, § 12:
Religious Discrimination 69 (2008) (providing as an example of a reasonable accommodation, a Wisconsin pharmacy's agreement to allow a pharmacist, who objected to dispensing contra-ception, to signal a coworker to serve customers seeking contraception)). 167. See Letter from Rick Pollack to Michael O. Leavitt, supra note 151, at 1 (describing necessity of health-care professionals working together to ensure that, in fulfilling their respons-ibility as employers to make reasonable accommodations of employees' religious beliefs, they are able to provide alternatives so that their obligations to provide timely patient access to care are met).
Fall 2010] TOWARDS PATIENT-CENTERED CARE 185
D. Provider Education
Providers must understand their professional and legal obliga-
tions, as well as the scope of the protections that apply to them, so
that they may protect their ability to participate in or refuse par-
ticipation in particular services while ensuring that the patient is
not harmed by their or the institution's refusal.168 Unfortunately,
current medical ethics and legal protections are often in tension, with
medical ethics requiring practitioners to focus on ensuring that the
patient is not harmed by the professional's moral beliefs, while many
legal norms shift responsibility for any patient harm that does result
from refusals away from the refusing practitioner and towards the
patient. One benefit to realigning legal standards with ethical require-
ments, as described supra Part I.A., so that medical professionals
unambiguously have a duty to put the patient first is that keeping the
burden of refusals on medical professionals incentivizes the medical
professions, which have control over refusal policy in a way that
patients do not, to craft careful policies that protect patient welfare
and protect the practitioner's conscience. For example, professionals
who know that they must always treat a patient in an emergency if
there is no other provider available, even if they have a moral ob-
jection, have an incentive to support the training, hiring, and peaceful
coexistence of non-objecting providers in their communities and
practice settings.
Whether objecting practitioners are legally exempt from liability
and disciplinary action for failure to provide services or not, medical
ethics still requires them to ensure that their moral beliefs do not
prevent any patient from exercising her right to make informed
medical decisions. Medical associations and boards should ensure that
their ethical opinions and the applicable standards of care for contro-
versial procedures are widely known by providers. In order to mini-
mize situations in which a provider will have to act against his con-
science, providers and their professional associations should take a
proactive role in ensuring that all communities have sufficient profess-
ionals willing to provide comprehensive services so that no provider
Stulberg et al., supra note 77, at 730 ("Hospital administrators may wish to better
involve physicians in the policy-making process, communicate policies more clearly, and develop means of hearing and accommodating physician concerns in order to reduce conflict and its impact on patient care.").
AVE MARIA LAW REVIEW
who objects will be forced to participate because a patient is in need
and no other provider is available.169
Doctors need information about what it means to practice in
religiously affiliated settings and how it limits their ability to practice
medicine according to the generally applicable standard of care so
that they can recognize and evaluate the legal and professional impli-
cations of institutional refusals, choose a practice setting that will
allow them to provide the full array of services they are willing to
provide and advocate for their patients.170 They also need to be aware
of limitations on the institution and individual's ability to refuse to
provide information and emergency services. In addition, providers,
especially pharmacists, need education about the medical services
they are charged with providing, particularly regarding the mechanism
of action of emergency contraception, so that they can give accurate
information and avoid unnecessary refusals based on lack of know-
ledge.171 Knowledge of their professional ethical and legal duties, such
as the legal duty to provide all information patients need to make
treatment decisions or the duty in some states for pharmacists to
provide prescription contraception, allows providers to protect them-
selves and their employers from malpractice suits.172
Finally, practioners need education about the protection available
to them through conscience laws and Title VII and the limitations
of these protections. This knowledge should encourage providers to
give their employers and patients notice of their religious restrictions
so that the health-care setting can ensure seamless patient services
while providing maximum accommodations to the provider. Clear
expectations that individual providers' beliefs will be accommodated
through means that do not compromise patient access allow medical
See Sonfield, supra note 163, at 10.
FOSTER ET AL., supra note 34, at 24 ("Although participants in our study demonstrated
considerable awareness that the Directives prohibit the provision of comprehensive contraception and abortion services, far fewer drew an explicit connection between the Directives and ectopic pregnancy and miscarriage management. Highlighting this link to clinicians may help raise awareness about the impact of mergers on their professional autonomy regarding a wider array of reproductive health issues."); see also Fogel & Rivera, supra note 45, at 725 (illustrating that when Catholic Healthcare West purchased the only hospital in Gilroy, Cal., doctors had to stop performing sterilizations and abortions, and family planning supplies and contraception were no longer available at the hospital or in the emergency room). 171. Am. Pub. Health Ass'n, supra note 24 ("The education of pharmacists about emergency contraception, particularly its time frame of effectiveness and mechanism of action, has also been identified as a critical need."); see also Varughese, supra note 2, at 660 (discussing the beliefs of some pharmacists regarding mechanisms of action of emergency contraception). 172.
NAT'L WOMEN'S LAW CTR., supra note 83, at 4–5.
Fall 2010] TOWARDS PATIENT-CENTERED CARE 187
professionals to step away from services that violate their consciences
without imposing the burdens of the providers' beliefs on the patient,
thus allowing providers to fulfill their professional duties without
violating their personal beliefs.
Source: http://avemarialaw-law-review.avemarialaw.edu/Content/articles/AMLR.v9i1.morrison.pdf
Document downloaded from http://www.revespcardiol.org, day 07/10/2016. This copy is for personal use. Any transmission of this document by any media or format is strictly prohibited. Rosuvastatin and Metformin Decrease Inflammation andOxidative Stress in Patients With Hypertension and DyslipidemiaAnel Gómez-García,a Gloria Martínez Torres,b Luz E. Ortega-Pierres,c Ernesto Rodríguez-Ayala,band Cleto Álvarez-Aguilard
Guidelines for the Use of Mifepristone for Medical Abortion in New Zealand Abbreviations used in this document.61. Introduction.72. Background.7 2.1 Approval of mifepristone (Mifegyne) in New Zealand.72.2 Legal requirements.7 3. Second Trimester Abortion.8 3.1 Background.83.2 Mifepristone dosage.83.3 The prostaglandin.83.4Interval between mifepristone and the prostaglandin.93.5 Second trimester protocols.9